Skip to main content

Why have Criminal Law at All?

  • Chapter
Retribution Reconsidered

Part of the book series: Philosophical Studies Series ((PSSP,volume 54))

Abstract

The core punishments of the criminal law (deprivation of liberty or life) represent gravely serious assaults on the fundamental rights of persons, stigmatize and humiliate those persons, and typically cause those persons great personal unhappiness. Even when punishments are not actually inflicted on a particular individual, the possibility that they might be inflicted may be sufficient to generate enough fear in that individual to cause him to refrain from acting in ways he otherwise would have found desirable—a coercive curtailment of his liberty.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Jeffrie G. Murphy, “Blackmail: A Preliminary Inquiry,” The Monist 63 (1980):156.This essay is reprinted in the present collection.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  2. The following distinctions are drawn from Guido Calabresi and A. Douglas Malamed, “Property Rules, Liability Rules, and Inalienability: One View of the Cathedral,” Harvard Law Review 85 (1972):1089. For applications of this distinction to the problem of criminalization (applications that have influenced the present discussion),

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. see Alvin Klevorick’s “The Economics of Crime” and Jules Coleman’s “Crime, Kickers and Transaction Stnuctures,” both in NOMOS XXVII: Criminal Justice, eds. J. Roland Pennock and John Chapman (New York: New York University Press, 1984).

    Google Scholar 

  4. In Anarchy, State and Utopia (New York: Basic Books, 1974), Robert Nozick describes our rights as defining an area of “moral space” around each of us and describes rights violations as “border crossings” or “boundary crossings. “These are powerful metaphors that give one—atleast initially—agood intuitive feel for the nature of rights. For an argument that Nozick’s way of thinking of rights ultimately will not work, see Robert Paul Wolff, “Robert Nozick’s Derivation of the Minimal State,” Arizona Law Review 19 (1977):7.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Supra, note 3, 55 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  6. It is perhaps easy to see why we might want absolute prohibitions against others crossing the borders defined by our right to life. But why are we prevented from selling our lives or allowing others to kill us with our consent? Are the reasons here ultimately ones of policy (how would we ever know if consent was really given if the victim was dead?) or are there reasons of principle?

    Google Scholar 

  7. It is of course possible that, at least for some crimes, criminal conviction and punishment represent society’s way of expressing moral condemnation for the act and reinforcing its own moral code. My point is simply that this cannot be the primary purpose of the criminal law nor is such a purpose limited to the criminal law. (This certainly does seem to be an indirect, costly, and hurtful way to express something!) For a good discussion of these matters, see Joel Feinberg, “The Expressive Function of Punishment,” The Monist 49 (1965).

    Google Scholar 

  8. This “social contract” way of thinking of the formation and legitimacy of government strikes me as a good metaphor for gaining insights on the purposes of government and the reasons we might have for adopting one or giving one our allegiance. Unlike some of its defenders, however, I do not think such a model proves either the rationality or the moral legitimacy of government.

    Google Scholar 

  9. The metaphor of the state as a “dominant protective agency” that we might actually hire to do a job for us (much as we might hire a plumber) is drawn from Nozick, supra note 3. This model faces serious problems (see Wolff, supra note 3) but it does have the marvelous feature of demythologizing government and the state.

    Google Scholar 

  10. For a powerful case that criminal law functions to prevent persons from bypassing an efficient and established market, see Richard Posner, Economic Analysis of Law (Boston: Little, Brown, 1972), chap. 4. This works clearly for property crimes, but it seems counterintuitive for crimes of personal violence, e.g.,rape. (What is the rape market that the rapist bypasses?) For more on this, see my “The Justice of Economics” (reprinted in this collection).

    Google Scholar 

  11. This is not, of course, to say that the intention of the criminal is usurpation. The criminal is no doubt typically motivated by greed and malice and does not see himself in political terms—i.e., as a revolutionary.

    Google Scholar 

  12. See the discussion of free expression and its relation to libel and slander in Chapter 2 of The Philosophy of Law: An Introduction to Jurisprudence, by Jeffrie G. Murphy and Jules L. Coleman (Boulder: Westview Press, Revised Edition, 1990).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1992 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Murphy, J.G. (1992). Why have Criminal Law at All?. In: Retribution Reconsidered. Philosophical Studies Series, vol 54. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-7922-3_1

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-7922-3_1

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-4170-8

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-015-7922-3

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics