Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Synthese Historical Library ((SYHL,volume 25))

Abstract

Gersonides, writing in fourteenth-century France, offers an interesting and provocative analysis of the problems inherent in prophecy and its relation to divine omniscience.1 This cluster of problems can be summarized as follows. Many scriptural prophecies concern contingent events. Hence the existence of prophetic statements about future contingent events suggests that these events can be foreknown. If they are foreknown how can they be contingent? And yet if they are not foreknown, how can the events in question be prophesied? In short, what sense can we make of prophetic statements which purport to relate information about future contingent events?2

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. The philosophical questions raised by Gersonides (Levi ben Gerson, 1288–1344), are contained in his major work Sefer Milḥamot Adonai (Wars of the Lord), Leipzig 1866. A recent English translation of book three of this work can be found in Gersonides: The Wars of the Lord; Treatise Three: On God’s Knowledge, translated by N. Samuelson, University of Toronto Press, Toronto 1977. In this paper references will be made both to the Hebrew edition (Milḥamot), as well as to Samuelson’s translation (Wars). In both cases reference will be made to treatise, chapter, and page number. For an extensive bibliography of scholarly works on Levi ben Gerson, cf. M. Kellner, ‘R. Levi ben Gerson: A Bibliographical Essay’, Studies in Bibliography and Booklore 12 (1979), pp. 13–23. References to specific articles will be made in the present essay when relevant;

    Google Scholar 

  2. however, the following works should be noted for their treatment of Gersonides’ theory of divine omniscience: N. Samuelson, ‘Gersonides’ Account of God’s Knowledge of Particulars’, Journal of the History of Philosophy 10 (1972), pp. 399–416;

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. T. M. Rudavsky, ‘Divine Omniscience and Future Contingents in Gersonides’, Journal of the History of Philosophy 21 (1983), pp. 513–536;

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. C. Sirat, Les théories des visions surnaturelles dans la pensée juive du’ moyen-âge, E. J. Brill, Leiden 1969;

    Google Scholar 

  5. C. Toutai, La Pensée Philosophique et Théologique de Gersonides, Les Editions de Minuit, Paris 1973;

    Google Scholar 

  6. Gersonides, Les Guerres du Seigneur, Livres III, et IV, translated by C. Touati, Mouton, Paris 1969.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Gersonides presents a modified version of the problem of prophecy in Milḥamot II.1.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Allusions to the problem of divine omniscience occur in other contexts as well, most notably when Gersonides is discussing issues connected with prophecy and divine providence. For these discussions, cf. Gersonides’ commentary on Job, in A. L. Lassen, The Commentary of Levi ben Gershon on the Book of Job, Bloch Publishing Co., New York 1946; and

    Google Scholar 

  9. in A. Altmann, ‘Gersonides’ Commentary on Averroes’ Epitome of Parva Naturalia II.3’, PAAJR 66–67 (1979–1980), pp. 1–31 (henceforth referred to as Altmann).

    Google Scholar 

  10. Milḥamot II.2, p. 94.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Milḥamot II.2, p. 95.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Altmann, op. cit., pp. 17–18.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Gersonides, Supercommentary on Averroes’ Commentary on Aristotle’s De Interpretatione, Chapter 9 (found in the 1562 edition of Aristotelis omnia quas extant opera... Averrois Cordubensis in ea opera omnes qui ad haec usque tempora pervenere commentarii... cum Levi Gersonidis in libros logicos annotationibus... a Iacob Mantino in Latinum conversi... Venetiis, apud Iunctas, MDLXII (vol. I, ff. 82vbK — 83rbF). An English translation of this portion of Averroes’ commentary and Gersonides’ supercommentary has been prepared by Professor N. Kretzmann. The quoted passage is found in 83rb D 46ff.

    Google Scholar 

  14. This distinction will allow Gersonides to maintain that the objects of prophetic knowledge are determined and structured from one standpoint, and undetermined and unstructured from another standpoint: “The aspect from which they are determined and structured is that of the heavenly bodies... the aspect in which they are contingents, i.e., indeterminate and unstructured, is that of our intellect and will”. Cf. Milḥamot II.2, pp. 96ff.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Milḥamot II.2, p. 97.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Milḥamot II.2, p. 96.

    Google Scholar 

  17. A similar point is made by Thomas Aquinas. In his Summa Contra Gentiles Bk III, ch. 41, Thomas maintains that only man’s body is subject to the stars; his intellect is subject to intellectual substances, while man’s will is subject to God’s influence. Cf. also Ibid. Bk. III ch. 84; D. W. Silverman, The Problem of Prophecy in Gersonides, PhD dissertation, Columbia University, 1975, p. 103.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Milḥamot IV.3, pp. 160–161.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Milḥamot II.2, p. 96. 14 Cf. Gersonides’ Supercommentary on Averroes’ Commentary on Aristotle’s De Interpretatione, Chapter 9, 83 raA 11. 5–10.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Wars III.4, p. 232.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Wars III.1, pp. 99–100.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Wars III.4, pp. 233–234.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Wars III.4, pp. 235–236. Abraham Ibn Daud, in his work Sefer-ha-Emunah ha-Ramah (The Exalted Faith), edited by S. Weil, Frankfurt 1852, (II, vi, 2, p. 96), develops a similar view according to which God’s lack of knowledge of future contingents is not a deficiency in him. For a discussion of the historical importance of Ibn Daud’s position, cf. S. Pines, ‘Scholasticism after Thomas Aquinas and the Teachings of Hasdai Crescas and his Predecessors’, Proceedings of the Israel Academy of Sciences and Humanities, vol. 1, no. 10, (1967), pp. 90ff.

    Google Scholar 

  24. For an elaboration of this critique, see my paper ‘Divine Omniscience and Future Contingents in Gersonides’, op. cit.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Gersonides’ Supercommentary on Averroes’ Commentary on Aristotle’s De Interpretatione, Chapter 9, 82vbK 34–36.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Ibid. 82vbL 15.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Averroes’ position is stated in his Qissur Sefer Ha-Ḥush We-Ha-Muḥash Le-Ibn Rushd, H. Blumberg (ed.), Medieval Academy of America, Cambridge 1954. Blumberg’s English translation of this work — henceforth called Blumberg — is found in his Averroes’ Epitome of Parva Naturalia, Cambridge, Medieval Academy of America, 1961.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Gersonides summarized and rejected Averroes’ position in Milḥamot II.2, p. 95.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Milḥamot II.2, p. 95.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Milḥamot II.2, p. 94.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Milḥamot II.2, pp. 94–95.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Milḥamot II.6, p. 104.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Blumberg, op. cit., p. 43.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Blumberg, op. cit., p. 46.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Milḥamot II.6, p. 106.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Milḥamot II.6, pp. 105–106.

    Google Scholar 

  39. In elucidating the process of prophecy, Samuelson employs the analogy of a radio station which transmits messages from a great distance. These messages can be received by anybody who satisfies the requisite criteria, ie has a strong enough receiver, has no local competing stations, etc. See Samuelson, op. cit. pp. 285–6.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Samuelson discusses Gersonides’ example in his introductory comments to Wars. Cf. Wars, pp. 50, 238.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Wars III.5, p. 286.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Milḥamot VI, Pt. 2, ch. 13, p. 460.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Milḥamot VI, Pt. 2, ch. 13, p. 461.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Ibid. “It is likely that a prophet may be tested completely if (the predicted event) does not occur. Then it can be truly seen that he is not a prophet; for if the good was ordained from the aspect of the heavenly bodies, it is unlikely that it would not occur. However, if the (predicted) good does occur, this is not sufficient to show that he is a prophet, for it is possible that it be conveyed in divination or in a dream”.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Milḥamot VI, Pt. 2, ch. 13, p. 461.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Gersonides discusses this example in Milḥamot VI, Pt. 2, ch. 13, pp. 461–462. An analogous discussion occurs in his Commentary on the Pentateuch, Exodus 32:10, Venice 1547.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Touati, op. cit., p. 463.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Milḥamot II.2, p. 94.

    Google Scholar 

  52. For recent discussions of the status of conditionals, cf. the collection of articles edited by E. Sosa, Causation and Conditionals, Oxford University Press, Oxford 1975.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Cf. J. Pollock, Subjunctive Reasoning, D. Reidel, Dordrecht 1976, pp. 25–44 for these and other examples.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  54. For recent discussion of this prophecy in late scholastic sources, cf. R. M. Adams, ‘Middle Knowledge and the Problem of Evil’, American Philosophical Quarterly 14 (1977), pp. 109–117. In this paper, Adams is concerned primarily with the formulations of Suarez and Molina.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Cf. Abraham Ibn Daud, Sefer-ha-Emunah ha-Ramah, ed. by S. Weil, Frankfurt A. M., 1852, II vi, 2 p. 97. In this work, Ibn Daud develops a view of divine omniscience similar to that of Gersonides; although he does not fully expand the implications of his theory with respect to prophecy, it is interesting to note this one implication. Pines has suggested a possible influence between Ibn Daud and Gersonides; cf S. Pines, op. cit., pp. 91ff.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Pollock, op. cit., pp. 31ff.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1985 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Rudavsky, T. (1985). Divine Omniscience, Contingency and Prophecy in Gersonides. In: Rudavsky, T. (eds) Divine Omniscience and Omnipotence in Medieval Philosophy. Synthese Historical Library, vol 25. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-7719-9_10

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-7719-9_10

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-8395-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-015-7719-9

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics