Skip to main content

Cognitivism and the Problem of Explaining Human Intelligence

  • Chapter
Culture and Cultural Entities

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 170))

  • 78 Accesses

Abstract

The explanation of intelligent behavior is an issue of the greatest strategic importance in any attempt to understand the conceptual features of the psychological, social, and cultural sciences. It is, however, too global an issue to be usefully confronted without substantial constraints. For example, a sensible beginning suggests that analysis should be at least initially restricted to the linguistically informed behavior of human beings, avoiding generalizations ranging over nonlanguage-using animals. In any case, it may be argued that the study of animal intelligence is conceptually dependent on the use of categories paradigmatically provided for the study of human intelligence. This, of course, is not to say that only humans describe animal intelligence . It is to say (rather) that animal intelligence is modelled on the human, in the sense that intelligence entails the ascription of propositional attitudes and that the structure of the propositional content of such attitudes is, and must be, modelled on sentences. Similarly, the issue may be fairly freed from the question of physicalistic reduction, in the plain sense that, should reductionism obtain, the phenomena of human intelligence would remain psychologically real, and the very success of any reductive effort would initially concede the apparent distinction of the phenomena thus reduced.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 74.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. See John Haugeland, ‘The Nature and Plausibility of Cognitivism’, The Behavioral and Brain Sciences, II (1978).

    Google Scholar 

  2. See Daniel Dennett, Content and Consciousness (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1969); Brainstorms (Montgomery, Vt.: Bradford Books, 1978).

    Google Scholar 

  3. Jerry A. Fodor, The Language of Thought (New York: Thomas Y. Crowell, 1975).

    Google Scholar 

  4. Michael Polanyi, Personal Knowledge, corr. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1962).

    Google Scholar 

  5. Maurice Merleau-Ponty, Phenomenology of Perception, Colin Smith (transl.) (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1962).

    Google Scholar 

  6. See Massimo Piattelli-Palmarini (ed.), Language and Learning: The Debate between Jean Piaget and Noam Chomsky (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1980).

    Google Scholar 

  7. Noam Chomsky, Rules and Representations (New York: Columbia University Press, 1980);

    Google Scholar 

  8. Jean Piaget, Structuralism, trans. Chininah Maschler (New York: Basic Books, 1970).

    Google Scholar 

  9. A full discussion of these views and of the cognitivist program is provided in Joseph Margolis, Philosophy of Psychology (Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall, 1984).

    Google Scholar 

  10. Cf. Joseph Margolis, ‘The Trouble with Homuncular Theories’, Philosophy of Science, XLVII (1980).

    Google Scholar 

  11. H. P. Grice, ‘Utterer’s Meaning and Intentions’, Philosophical Review, LXXVIII (1969), 151. Cf. also, ‘Meaning’, Philosophical Review, LXVII (1957); and ‘Utterer’s Meaning, Sentence-Meaning, and Word-Meaning’, Foundations of Language, IV (1968).

    Google Scholar 

  12. This explains, perhaps, Daniel Dennett’s attraction to Grice’s thesis; cf. ‘Conditions of Personhood’, in Amélie Oksenberg Rorty (ed.), The Identities of Persons (Berkeley: University of California Press ,1976).

    Google Scholar 

  13. ‘Utterer’s Meaning, Sentence-Meaning, and Word-Meaning’.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Grice characteristically shifts from the intentional to the intensional, though he never explains or justifies the turn. Whether the change is benign enough is itself a matter of argument; cf. for example, James Cornman, ‘Intentionality and Intensionality’, Philosophical Quarterly, XII (1962).

    Google Scholar 

  15. Cf. Joseph Margolis, ‘Meaning, Speakers’ Intentions, and Speech Acts,’ Review of Metaphysics, XXVI (1973); and 7, below;

    Google Scholar 

  16. also, Hilary Putnam, The Meaning of “Meaning”, in Philosophical Papers, Vol. 2 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1975); Meaning and the Moral Sciences (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1978).

    Google Scholar 

  17. Louis Hjelmslev, Prolegomena to a Theory of Language, rev. trans. Francis J. Whitfield (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1961), p. 9.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Ferdinand de Saussure, Course in General Linguistics, Wade Baskin (transl.), Charles Bally, Albert Sechehaye, Albert Riedlinger (eds.) (New York: Philosophical Library, 1959), pp. 13–14. Page references are to the McGraw-Hill paperback edition, 1966.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Noam Chomsky, Language and Responsibility, John Viertel (transl.) (New York: Pantheon Books, 1979), pp . 140,15 2–15 3.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Hjelmslev, op. cit., 14.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Ibid., p. 14–15; cf. pp. 39–40.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Cf. ibid., pp. 21–23.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Hilary Putnam, ‘The Nature of Mental States’, in Philosophical Papers, Vol. 2.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Loc. cit.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Cf. ibid., p. 5–6 . Contrast Fodor, loc. cit., and Dennett, loc. cit.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Alfred Tarski, ‘The Semantic Conception of Truth’, Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, IV (1944). Donald Davidson has, more recently, attempted to sketch a theory in which Tarski’s account could be directly applied to natural languages, though the venture seems essentially programmatic; cf. for instance, ‘In Defense of Convention T’, in Hugues Leblanc (ed.), Truth, Syntax and Modality (Amsterdam: North Holland, 1975); and ‘Truth and Meaning’, Synthese, XVII (1967). For a favorable and unfavorable appraisal of Davidson’s account, see Gareth Evans and John McDowell (eds.), Truth and Meaning (Oxford: Clarendon, 1976); and Ian Hacking, Why Does Language Matter to Philosophy? (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1975).

    Google Scholar 

  27. Michael A. Arbib and David Caplan, ‘Neurolinguistics Must be Computational’, The Behavioral and Brain Sciences, II (1979). Their commentators take them to task for this, though one at least (D. Langendoen) argues that “linguistics must be computational too” (470): Cf. ‘One Author’s Response’ (Arbib), ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Loc. cit.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Cf. Margolis , Philosophy of Psychology.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Saussure, op. cit., pp . 81, 84 .

    Google Scholar 

  31. Ibid., p. 84.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Ibid., p. 85.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Loc. cit.

    Google Scholar 

  34. This general view of Saussure corresponds to the extremely perceptive account that Roland Barthesaffords, in Elements of Semiology, Annette Lavers and Colin Smith (transl.) (New York: Hill and Wang, 1967), particularly pp. 15–22. (Page references are to the paperback edition.)

    Google Scholar 

  35. Saussure, op. cit., p. 14.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Ibid., p. 110.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Loc. cit.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Pierre Bourdieu, Outline of a Theory of Practice, trans. Richard Nice (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1977).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  39. Loc. cit.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Thomas S. Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, 2nd ed. enl. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1970).

    Google Scholar 

  41. Possibly the most extreme — curiously similar — opposition to the possibility of a rational method appears in the work of Paul Feyerabend and Jacques Derrida. See, for instance, Paul Feyerabend, Against Method (London: NLB, 1975),

    Google Scholar 

  42. and Jacques Derrida, Speech and Phenomena, trans. David B. Allison (Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 1973).

    Google Scholar 

  43. Cf. Joseph Margolis, ‘Wissenschaftliche Methoden und Feyerabends Plädoyer für den Anarchismus’, in Versuchungen, Aufsätze zur Philosophie Paul Feyerabends, heraus. Hans Peter Duerr (Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1981).

    Google Scholar 

  44. Noam Chomsky, Language and Mind, enl. ed. (New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1972). p. 83.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Cf. Jonathan Culler, Sturcturalist Poetics (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1975), Ch. 10. Culler considers chiefly the work of Roland Barthes, Jacques Derrida, and Julia Kristeva, in which — sometimes equivocally, the denial of a generative and interpretive system and the proposal of a système décentré are conflated.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  46. For example, Chomsky remarks, contrasting his own view with that of Foucault, that “He [that is, Foucault ] is, I believe, skeptical about the possibility or the legitimacy of an attempt to place important sources of human knowledge within the human mind, conceived in an ahistorical manner,” Language and Responsibility, p. 75.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Language and Mind, p. 71.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Cf. Language and Responsibility, p. 128; also, Justin Leiber, Noam Chomsky (New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1975), pp. 64–68

    Google Scholar 

  49. and Ned Block, ‘Troubles with Functionalism’, in C. Wade Savage (ed.), Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. IX (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1978).

    Google Scholar 

  50. Cf.Language and Mind, pp. 180–185.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Loc. cit.

    Google Scholar 

  52. For an illuminating discussion of the issue, see D. W. Hamlyn, Experience and the Growth of Understanding (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1978), Chapter 7–8.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Cf. Noam Chomsky, Syntactic Structures (The Hague: Mouton, 1959), Ch. 2.

    Google Scholar 

  54. Language and Responsibility, pp. 148–154. Cf. Leiber, op. cit. p. 122.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Ibid., p. 193.

    Google Scholar 

  56. J. J. Gibson, The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception (Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1979); and The Senses Considered as Perceptual Systems (Boston: Houghton Mifflin, 1966).

    Google Scholar 

  57. The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception, p. 2.

    Google Scholar 

  58. Cf. Ulric Neisser, Cognition and Reality (San Francisco: W. H. Freeman, 1976).

    Google Scholar 

  59. The Ecological Approach to Visual Perception, p. 141.

    Google Scholar 

  60. Ibid., pp. 140, 127. The concept of “affordance” is Gibson’s adjusted interpretation of the Gestaltist notion, Aufforderungscharakter (sometimes translated “valence”). Cf. p. 138.

    Google Scholar 

  61. Ibid., p. 129.

    Google Scholar 

  62. Ibid ., p . 130.

    Google Scholar 

  63. Cf. ibid., Chapter 15; also, J. J. Gibson, ‘The Information Available in Pictures,’ Leonardo, IV (1971); and ‘On the Concept of Formless Invariants in Visual Perception’, Leonardo, VI (1973).

    Google Scholar 

  64. Thus Gibson, ibid.: “What modern painters are trying to do, if they only knew it, is paint invariants” (p. 284); “But the essence of a picture is just that its information is not explicit” (p. 285). Cf. Nelson Goodman, Languages of Art (Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Co ., 1968).

    Google Scholar 

  65. Chomsky,Rules and Representations, pp. 69–70.

    Google Scholar 

  66. Fodor, The Language of Thought; cf. also, ‘On the Impossibility of Acquiring “More Powerful” Structures’, in Massimo Piattelli-Palmarini (ed.), Language and Learning: the Debate Between Jean Piaget and Noam Chomsky (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1980).

    Google Scholar 

  67. Op. cit., p. 142.

    Google Scholar 

  68. Ibid ., p. 143.

    Google Scholar 

  69. N. Tinbergen, The Study of Instinct (New York: Oxford University Press, 1951, 1969).

    Google Scholar 

  70. Konrad Lorenz, Studies in Animal and Human Behavior, 2 vols ., trans . Robert Martin (Cambridge : Harvard University Press, 1970, 1971).

    Google Scholar 

  71. Karl von Frisch, The Dance Language and Orientation of Bees, trans. Leigh E. Chadwick (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1967).

    Google Scholar 

  72. Tinbergen, op. cit., p. 110.

    Google Scholar 

  73. Ibid ., pp. 41 —42 .

    Google Scholar 

  74. Ibid., pp. 25–37.

    Google Scholar 

  75. Bert Hölldobler, ‘Communication in Social Hymenoptera,’ in Thomas A. Sebeok (ed.), How Animals Communicate (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1977), p.418.

    Google Scholar 

  76. Cf. Karl von Frisch, loc. cit.; J. L. Gould, ‘Honey Bee Communication: Misdirection of Recruits by Foragers with Covered Ocelli,’ Nature, CCLII (1974); J. L. Gould, ‘Honey Bee Recruitment : The Dance-Language Controversy’, Science, CLXXXIX (1975).

    Google Scholar 

  77. Hölldobler, op. cit., p. 449; Hölldobler mentions particularly, here, the work of H. Montagner, Comportements trophallactiques chez les guépes sociales (Paris: Service du Film de Recherche Scientifiique, Film no. B2053).

    Google Scholar 

  78. Donald R. Griffim, ‘Prospects for a Cognitive Ethology’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences, IV (1978), 535 .

    Google Scholar 

  79. Cf. Donald R. Griffin, The Question of Animal Awareness (New York: Rockefeller University Press, 1976).

    Google Scholar 

  80. Loc. cit.

    Google Scholar 

  81. There is some justification for so speaking, at the level of sponges, the Portuguese man-o -war, social amoebae, and the like — even of termites and honey bees. But the fact that the genetics of populations is not straightforwardly reducible to the genetics of aggregated individuals does not entail that populations constitute real biological organisms of any sort. Cf. Theodosius Dobzhansky, Genetics of the Evolutionary Process (New York: Columbia University Press, 1970); Mankind Evolving (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1962).

    Google Scholar 

  82. ‘Part and Parcel in Animal and Human Societies’, op. cit., Vol. 2, p. 147; cf. also, ‘A Consideration of Methods of Identification of Species-specifiic Instinctive Behavior Patterns in Birds’, op. cit., Vol. 1.

    Google Scholar 

  83. See Margolis, Philosophy of Psychology. Cf. Pylyshyn, ‘Computational Models and Empirical Constraints’, Behavioral and Brain Sciences, I (1978); also, the ‘Open Peer Commentary’ and ‘Author’s Response’; Noam Chomsky, Reflections on Language (New York: Pantheon, 1975);

    Google Scholar 

  84. and Hubert L. Dreyfus, What Computers Can’t Do, rev. ed. (New York: Harper and Row, 1979), especially the introduction to the revised edition.

    Google Scholar 

  85. Cf. for instance, J. D. Miller, ‘Speech Perception by the Chinchilla: Viiced-voiceless Distinction in Alveolar Plosive Consonants’, Science, CXC (1975); and A. M. Liberman et al., ‘Perception of the Speech Code’, Psychological Review, LXXIV (1967).

    Google Scholar 

  86. Noam Chomsky, Rules and Representations, p. 65.

    Google Scholar 

  87. Cf. Bourdieu, op.cit.: and Lucien Goldmann, Essays on Method in the Sociology of Literature, William Q. Boelhower (transl.) (St. Louis: Telos Press, 1980).

    Google Scholar 

  88. Claude Lévi-Strauss, The Raw and the Cooked, trans. John and Doreen Weightman (New York: Harper and Row, 1969), p. 12.

    Google Scholar 

  89. Ludwig Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, G. E. M. Anscombe (transl.) (New York: Macmillan, 1953), § 81.

    Google Scholar 

  90. Ibid., § 242.

    Google Scholar 

  91. Cf. Hamlyn, op. cit., Chapter 6.

    Google Scholar 

  92. Cf. L. S. Vygotsky, Thought and Language, trans. Eugenia Hanfmann and Gertrude Vakar (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1962).

    Book  Google Scholar 

  93. Lorenz, ‘Part and Parcel in Animal and Human Species’, pp. 147–148.

    Google Scholar 

  94. Bourdieu, op. cit., p. 78.

    Google Scholar 

  95. Loc. cit.

    Google Scholar 

  96. Ibid., p. 95.

    Google Scholar 

  97. See particularly Hans-Georg Gadamer, Truth and Method, trans. (from 2nd ed.), Garrett Barden and John Cumming (New York: Seabury Press, 1975);

    Google Scholar 

  98. and Paul Ricoeur, Interpretation Theory: Discourse and the Surplus of Meaning (Fort Worth: Texas Christian University Press, 1977). The latest remnant of (naive) romantic hermeneutics is represented by E. D. Hirsch, Jr., Validity in Interpretation (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1967); on Hirsch, cf. Joseph Margolis, Art and Philosophy (Atlantic Highlands: Humanities Press, 1980).

    Google Scholar 

  99. Cf. Donald Davidson, ‘Mental Events’, in Lawrence Foster and J. W. Swanson (eds.), Experience and Theory (Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press, 1970).

    Google Scholar 

  100. Roland Barthes, ‘From Work to Text’, trans. Josué V. Harari, in Josué V. Harari (ed), Textual Strategies; Perspectives in Post-Structuralist Criticism (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1979), p. 77.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1984 Joseph Margolis

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Margolis, J. (1984). Cognitivism and the Problem of Explaining Human Intelligence. In: Culture and Cultural Entities. Synthese Library, vol 170. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-7694-9_6

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-7694-9_6

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-015-7696-3

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-015-7694-9

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics