Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 170))

  • 74 Accesses

Abstract

“What made him insult her?” we ask. “What caused him to leave the country?” These are familiar locutions that invite — or appear to invite — causal explanations of human actions. The ease with which such questions arise and are answered suggests the ubiquity of causal explanation regarding the familiar range of human agency. They are not, in any obvious way, restricted to certain defective or deficient or metaphorically or legally extended forms of agency; they are normally entertained wherever we suppose human beings to be capable of the fullest freedom, liberty, choice, deliberate commitment in what they do. Still, there is a nagging and prolonged dispute among philosophers as to whether in principle human action — or at any rate, the actions of a so-called free agent, free actions, actions freely performed — may be explained in causal terms or must be explained in one or another contracausal way.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 74.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Cf. C. A. Campbell, ‘Is ‘Free Will’ a Pseudo Problem?’ Mind, LX (1951).

    Google Scholar 

  2. Cf. A. I. Melden, Free Action (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1961).

    Google Scholar 

  3. Donald Davidson, ‘Actions, Reasons and Causes’, Journal of Philosophy, LX (1963).

    Google Scholar 

  4. Cf. G. E. M. Anscombe, Intention (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1957).

    Google Scholar 

  5. Alvin I. Goldman, A Theory of Action (Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall, 1970).

    Google Scholar 

  6. Cf. Jaegwon Kim, ‘Causes and Counterfactuals’, Journal of Philosophy LXX (1973). This goes against Donald Davidson’s views about individuating actions (a subset of events); cf. Davidson, ‘The Individuation of Events’, in Nicholas Rescher (ed.), Essays in Honor of Carl Hempel (Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1970).

    Google Scholar 

  7. A Theory of Action, pp. 6 3–64. Nonbasic actions, therefore, are “generated” by basic acts that are caused (by the agent’s wants and beliefs).

    Google Scholar 

  8. See for instance ‘Mental Events’, in Lawrence Foster and J. W. Swanson (eds.), Experience and Theory (Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press, 1970);

    Google Scholar 

  9. Joseph Margolis, Persons and Minds (Dordrecht: D. Reidel, 1978), Chapter 11.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  10. These issues are developed chiefly in ‘Causal Relations’, Journal of Philosophy, LXIV (1967).

    Google Scholar 

  11. Davidson cites the following of Ducasse’s work: ‘Critique of Hume’s Conception of Causality’, Journal of Philosophy, LXIII (1966); Causation and the Types of Necessity (Seattle: University of Washington Press, 1924); Nature, Mind, and Death (LaSalle, Ill.: Open Court, 1951), Pt. II.

    Google Scholar 

  12. ‘Causal Relations’, 702.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Contrast Arthur C. Danto, for instance: Analytical Philosophy of Action (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973), p. 82.

    Google Scholar 

  14. ‘Causal Relations’, 700.

    Google Scholar 

  15. ‘Causal Relations’, 701.

    Google Scholar 

  16. ‘Causal Relations’, 699.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Thus Davidson’s interest in J. L. Mackie’s account, ‘Causes and Conditions’, A merican Philosophical Quarterly, II (1965).

    Google Scholar 

  18. ‘Mental Events’, p. 80f.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Cf. Persons and Minds, Chapter 11.

    Google Scholar 

  20. ‘Mental Events’, p. 81n.

    Google Scholar 

  21. ‘Mental Events’, p. 92.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Analytical Philosophy of Action, p. 98.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Cf. Joseph Margolis, Psychotherapy and Morality (New York: Random House, 1966), Chapter 4, particularly pp. 97 —98.

    Google Scholar 

  24. J. L. Austin, ‘Ifs and Cans’, reprinted in Philosophical Papers, J. O. Urmson and G. J. Warnock (eds.) (Oxford: Clarendon, 1961);

    Google Scholar 

  25. P. H. Nowell-Smith, Ethics (Harmondsworth: Penguin Books, 1954), Chapter 19.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Ethics, p. 282.

    Google Scholar 

  27. I can say, however, from a private conversation, that Austin was clearly interested in some form of contra-causal account.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Persons (New York: St. Martin’s Press, 1977). D. xii.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Gilbert Ryle, The Concept of Mind (London: Hutchinson, 1949).

    Google Scholar 

  30. Persons, p. 28.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Persons, p. 28.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Cf. ‘Actions. Reasons and Causes’.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Cf. Joseph Margolis, ‘Puzzles Regarding Explanation by Reasons and Explanation by Causes’, Journal of Philosophy, LXVII (1970).

    Google Scholar 

  34. ‘Mental Events’, pp. 87–88.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Cf. Roderick M. Chisholm, ‘Freedom and Action’, in Keith Lehrer (ed.), Freedom and Determinism (New York: Random House, 1966); also, Irving Thalberg, ‘Do We Cause Our Own Actions?’ Analysis, XXVII (1967).

    Google Scholar 

  36. Analytical Philosophy of Action, p. 72. Danto also speaks of “the chaos of the distinction”, p. 206. Cf. also, Donald Davidson, ‘Agency’, in Robert Binkley, Richard Bronaugh, and Ansonio Marras (eds.), Agent, Action, and Reason (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1971).

    Google Scholar 

  37. Analytical Philosophy of Action, p. 115.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Analytical Philosophy of Action, p. 184. Cf. Anthony Kenny, Will, Freedom and Power (Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 1975).

    Google Scholar 

  39. Analytical Philosophy of Action, p. 195.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Davidson’s list — formulated in terms of denying that “rationalization is a species of ordinary causal explanation”, being more suited to supporting a contra-causal theory of some sort — includes the following: G. E. M. Anscombe, Stuart Hampshire, H. L. A. Hart and A. M. Honoré, William Dray, Anthony Kenny, A. E. Melden (“and most of the books in the series edited by R. F. Holland, Studies in Philosophical Psychology”), ‘Actions, Reasons and Causes’, p. 685n.

    Google Scholar 

  41. ‘Agency’, p. 12.

    Google Scholar 

  42. ‘Agency’, p. 14.

    Google Scholar 

  43. ‘Agency’, p. 15.

    Google Scholar 

  44. ‘Agency’, p. 4.

    Google Scholar 

  45. The latter denial is defended at length in Persons and Minds, where the relationship of embodiment is contrasted with those of identity and composition.

    Google Scholar 

  46. ‘Agency’, p. 11.

    Google Scholar 

  47. ‘Agency’, p. 18.

    Google Scholar 

  48. ‘Agency’, p. 11.

    Google Scholar 

  49. ‘Agency’, p. 14.

    Google Scholar 

  50. ‘Agency’, p. 23.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Karl Marx, Grundrisse, Martin Nicolaus (transl.) (New York: Vintage, 1973).

    Google Scholar 

  52. Carol C. Gould, ‘Beyond Causality in the Social Sciences: Reciprocity as a Model of Non-exploitative Social Relations’, unpublished, first presented at The Boston Colloquium for the Philosophy of Science, Boston University, March 15, 1977.

    Google Scholar 

  53. See also, Carol C. Gould, Marx’s Social Ontology (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1978).

    Google Scholar 

  54. Cf. Wesley C. Salmon, ‘Statistical Explanation’, in Wesley C. Salmon et al., Statistical Explanation and Statistical Relevance (Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press, 1971);

    Google Scholar 

  55. also, Carl G. Hempel, ‘Aspects of Science Explanation’, in Aspects of Scientific Explanation and Other Essays in the Phitosophy of Science (New York: Free Press, 1965). Ernst Mayr reports a hundred evolutionary “laws” listed by Bernhard Rensch, which he says “refer to adaptive trends effected by natural selection. Most of them have occasional or frequent exceptions and are only ‘rules,’ not universal laws,” The Growth of Biological Thought (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1982), pp. 37–38.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Karl K. Popper, ‘The Aims of Science,’ in Objective Knowledge (Oxford: Clarendon, 1972), p. 196.

    Google Scholar 

  57. See Persons and Minds; also, Joseph Margolis, ‘Reconciling Freud’s Scientific Project and Psychoanalysis’, in Morals, Science and Sociality (The Foundations of Ethics and Its Relationship to Science, Vol. III), H. Tristram Engelhardt, Jr. and Daniel Callahan (eds.) (Hastings-on-Hudson: Institute of Society, Ethics and the Life Sciences. 1978).

    Google Scholar 

  58. This is certainly one way to construe Herbert Feigl’s candid admission of the problems of reductionism; cf. The ‘Mental’ and the ‘Physical’: The Essay and a Postscript (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1958, 1967).

    Google Scholar 

  59. ‘Actions, Reasons and Causes’.

    Google Scholar 

  60. ‘Agency’, p. 8.

    Google Scholar 

  61. Cf. however, Joseph Margolis, review of Goldman’s A Theory of Action, Metaphilosophy, V (1974).

    Google Scholar 

  62. Cf. ‘The Individuation of Events’.

    Google Scholar 

  63. Cf. ‘Reconciling Freud’s Scientifiic Project with Psychoanalysis’.

    Google Scholar 

  64. Cf. Peter Winch, The Idea of a Social Science (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1963);

    Google Scholar 

  65. Jürgen Habermas, Knowledge and Human Interests, Jeremy J. Shapiro (transl.) (Boston: Beacon Press, 1971);

    Google Scholar 

  66. Richard J. Bernstein, The Restructuring of Social and Political Theory (New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1976).

    Google Scholar 

  67. Reductionism is the key to Davidson’s ‘Mental Events’.

    Google Scholar 

  68. Cf. The Mental’ and the ‘Physical’; also Otto Neurath et al., International Encyclopedia of Unified Science, Vols. 1–2 (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1955).

    Google Scholar 

  69. ‘Actions, Reasons and Causes’.

    Google Scholar 

  70. Cf. for instance, Wesley Salmon, ‘Statistical Explanation’.

    Google Scholar 

  71. A. I. Melden, Free Action, p. 52. Cf. also, Charles Taylor, The Explanation of Behaviour (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1964).

    Google Scholar 

  72. There is an intriguing and not merely superficial resemblance here to H. P. Grice’s analysis of speaker’s meaning; cf. ‘Meaning’, Philosophical Review, LXVI (1957).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1984 Joseph Margolis

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Margolis, J. (1984). Action and Causality. In: Culture and Cultural Entities. Synthese Library, vol 170. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-7694-9_4

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-7694-9_4

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-015-7696-3

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-015-7694-9

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics