Skip to main content

Defining the Problem Situation

  • Chapter
Quantifying Music

Part of the book series: The University of Western Ontario Series in Philosophy of Science ((WONS,volume 23))

  • 183 Accesses

Abstract

When we listen to two musical sounds chosen at random, their successive or simultaneous impact on our hearing will in general not be pleasant: nearly all musical intervals are dissonances. However, when passing through this continuum of dissonances, we hit from time to time upon a combination of musical sounds which is not rough and unpleasant, but strikes us as sweet, restful, and pure; these intervals are the so-called consonances. Owing to this pleasant effect on our senses, consonances have become the next-to-universal building-blocks of music. In all Western music up to and partly including the 20th century, and in nearly all non-Western music as well, the selection of the notes to be used in the various tone scales has been guided primarily by the consonances, either melodically (one constituent tone of the interval heard after the other) or harmonically (both heard at the same time). Why is this so? Where do these exceptional intervals called ‘consonances’ come from?

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. See for a recent overview of the Pythagorean contribution to the problem of consonance Van der Waerden (1979), Ch. 16.

    Google Scholar 

  2. The connection between outer and inner harmony appears to be so self-evident in Greek thinking that this aspect of the problem of consonance is virtually never explicitly discussed. An example of this feeling of self-evidence is given in Plotinus, Enneads II, 9, 16. (I am grateful to Rein Ferwerda for providing me with both the information and the reference to Plotinus). See for an overview of ancient theories of consonance Stumpf (1901).

    Google Scholar 

  3. This cannot be the place to discuss the origins of the rise of polyphony and of the triad, which together informed Western music in a unique way, setting it apart from all other musical systems, primitive and otherwise. Beside the current music history textbooks like Grout’s and Reese’s, a fascinating essay by the sociologist Max Weber (1921) may be mentioned especially. See also Gut (1969).

    Google Scholar 

  4. Zarlino (15733), 28–34; cp. Zarlino (1571), 75; 92.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Salinas (1577), 67/8.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Cp. S. Themerson, Professor Mmaa’s lecture (London, 1953), 77–80; in particular Prof. Soul’s apt remark that, as this way of explaining things is both final and metaphysical, it does not call for further inquiry.

    Google Scholar 

  7. This oft-quoted phrase is not literally to be found in the Ed. Naz. It seems to be contaminated by Galileo’s famous statement in the Saggiatore (Ed. Naz. 6, 232): “La filosofía è scritta in questo grandissimo libro che continuamente ci sta aperto innanzi a li occhi (io dico ľuniverso), [...]. Egli è scritto in lingua matematica . . . “, and by Viviani’s biography of Galileo in which it is said of him (Ed. Naz. 19, 625), “che la liberta delia campagna fosse il libro della natura [...]; dicendo che i caratteri con che era scritto erano le proposizioni, figure e conclusioni geometriche, per il cui solo mezzo potevasi penetrare alcuno delli infiniti misterii dell’istessa natura”. Cp. also Ed. Naz. 18,295.

    Google Scholar 

  8. GW 6, 104/5: “Geometria enim [...], Deo coaeterna, inque Mente divina relucens, exempla Deo suppeditavit [.. .] exornandi Mundi, ut is fieret Optimus et Pulcherimus, denique Creatoris similimus”. Similar sentiments are expressed in Kepler’s work at many places, e.g. GW 1, 24; GW 13, 113; GW 14, 27; and GW 6, 279; “ . . . quod magis delector Geometria in Physicis rebus expressâ, quam abstractà illâ .. . “.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Dijksterhuis (1955) and (1961), passim; esp. the final line of the book (p. 501) that sums up the whole argument. Kuhn (1977), Ch. 3: ‘Mathematical Versus Experimental Traditions in the Development of Physical Science’, esp. 52–55.

    Google Scholar 

  10. It is well known that Newton himself did not find this new harmony quite so harmonious as later generations would: he never gave up the attempt to find a corpuscular substratum for the forces he worked with. Westfall’s thesis is to be found in his (19772), Introduction and Chs. 7/8.

    Google Scholar 

  11. GW 6, 94: “ . .. causae tarnen intervallorum latuerunt homines; adeò ut ante Pytha-goram ne quaererentur quidem; et quaesitas per duo millia annorum, primus ego, nisi fallor, exactissimè proferam”.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Ed. Naz. 8, 143: “... impero che stetti lungo tempo perplesso intorno a queste forme delle consonanze, non mi parendo che la ragione che comunemente se n’adduce da gli autori che sin qui hanno scritto dottamente della musica, fusse concludente a bastanza”. 146: “... potremo per awentura assegnar assai congrua ragione ondeawenga che di essi suoni, differenti di tuono, alcune coppie siano con gran diletto ricevute dal nostro sensorio, altre con minore, ed altre ci feriscano con grandissima molestia . . . “. The English is taken from the 1730 translation by Thomas Weston (see Note III, 24), 145,150/1.

    Google Scholar 

  13. JIB 4, 142: “Ipsissimus est D. des Chartes [...]. Ipsus, inquam, is est, cui ante decern annos ea quae de causis dulcedinis consonantiarum scripseram, communicavi

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1984 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Cohen, H.F. (1984). Defining the Problem Situation. In: Quantifying Music. The University of Western Ontario Series in Philosophy of Science, vol 23. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-7686-4_1

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-7686-4_1

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-8388-3

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-015-7686-4

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics