Skip to main content

The Evolution of Morality

  • Chapter
Morality in Evolution

Abstract

Bergson has described the closed society as static, circular, disciplined, caught up in automatism and organized for self-preservation. It represents a halt in the evolutionary process. The open society is dynamic, progressive, creative and characterized by freedom and universal charity. It represents a forward thrust. It is apparent that man has progressed beyond the state of the primitive closed society, and while he is still far from the ideal of the open society, morally he is advancing in that direction. How does this moral progress come about? Bergson answers the question in a remarkable analysis of the interacting relationship between the two moralities. The profound implications of his theory of knowledge are unfolded here, and perhaps nowhere else is the extraordinary originality and ingenuity of his moral doctrine, and the internal coherence of his whole philosophy, better revealed.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. The Two Sources, p. 55 (O. 1029).

    Google Scholar 

  2. Ibid., p. 76 (O. 1046–47). See Léon Husson, L’Intellectualisme de Bergson, pp. 194–207, especially p. 199, for a helpful discussion of the intellect’s function in morality.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Ibid., D. 57 (O. 1030 ).

    Google Scholar 

  4. Ibid., p. 57 (O. 1030 ). See also p. 87 (O. 1056–57): “… philosophers have misunderstood the compound nature of obligation in its present-day form: they have been led to attribute to this or that mental picture or operation the power of influencing the will: as if an idea could ever categorically demand its own realization! as if the idea were anything else, in this case, than an intellectual extract common to all, or, better still, the projection on to the intellectual plane of a whole set of tendencies and aspirations, some above, some beneath, pure intelligence!”

    Google Scholar 

  5. Ibid., O. 72 (O. 1043 ).

    Google Scholar 

  6. Ibid., P. 75 (O. 1046 ).

    Google Scholar 

  7. Ibid., p. 15 (O. 994): “Because in a reasonable being reason does indeed intervene as a regulator to assure this consistency between obligatory rules or maxims, philosophy has been led to look upon it as a principle of obligation.” See also p. 8o (O. 1050): “If certain really active forces, actually influencing our will, are already in possession, reason could and should intervene to co-ordinate their effects, but it could not contend with them, since one can always reason with reason, confront its arguments with others, or simply refuse all discussion…”

    Google Scholar 

  8. Ibid., p. 72 (O. 1043).

    Google Scholar 

  9. Ibid., p. 57 (O. to3o). See D. 41 (O. 1016–17): “These two moralities, placed side by side. appear now to be only one, the first having lent to the second something of its imperative character and having, on the other hand, received from it in exchange a connotation less strictly social, more broadly human.” And also pp. 42–43 (O. 1017–18): “Once again, there is some difficulty in comparing the two moralities because they are no longer to be found in a pure state. The first has handed on to the second something of its compulsive force; the second has diffused over the other something of its perfume.”

    Google Scholar 

  10. Ibid., p. 5o (O. 1024).

    Google Scholar 

  11. Ibid., pp. 50–51 (O. 1025).

    Google Scholar 

  12. Ibid., pp. 41–42 (O. 1016–17).

    Google Scholar 

  13. Ibid.. P. 75 (O. 1045–46).

    Google Scholar 

  14. Ibid., p. 256 (O. 1202).

    Google Scholar 

  15. Ibid.. pp. 60, 72, 73, 76 (O. 1033, 1043, 1044, 1047).

    Google Scholar 

  16. Ibid., pp. 60–76 (O. 1033–47).

    Google Scholar 

  17. Ibid., pp. 71–72 (O. 1043).

    Google Scholar 

  18. Ibid., p. 70 (O. 1041).

    Google Scholar 

  19. Ibid., p. 76 (O. 1047).

    Google Scholar 

  20. For Bergson’s critique of moral theories see ibid., pp. 86–99 (O. 1047–57).

    Google Scholar 

  21. Ibid., P. 77 (O. 2047 ).

    Google Scholar 

  22. Ibid., P. 78 (O. 2048–49).

    Google Scholar 

  23. Ibid., p. 82 (O. 1052).

    Google Scholar 

  24. Ibid., p. 8o (O. 1050–51).

    Google Scholar 

  25. Ibid.. pp. 85–86 (O. 1055).

    Google Scholar 

  26. In a painstaking study, E. Rolland attempts to demonstrate that each of the elements required for an authentic finalism is absent from Bergson’s moral philosophy. See La Finalité Morale dans le Bergsonisme (Paris: Gabriel Beauchesne, 1937), especially chapters IV and V.

    Google Scholar 

  27. The Two Sources, pp. 45–46, 48, 300–01 (O. 1020, 1022, 1240–41).

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1970 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Gallagher, I.J. (1970). The Evolution of Morality. In: Morality in Evolution. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-7573-7_8

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-7573-7_8

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-017-0034-4

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-015-7573-7

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics