Skip to main content

The Biological Origin of Moral Obligation

  • Chapter
  • 74 Accesses

Abstract

Go to experience, gather the facts, and let your theorizing never go beyond the data. This was Bergson’s method. In Time and Free Will and Matter and Memory he had considered certain psychological data. Creative Evolution was an interpretation of biological data. What does experience tell us now about morality? It tells us that there are two distinct forces at work in the moral life of man: (I) a pressure or constraint exerted by society upon its members, and (2) an appeal or attraction exercised by certain privileged souls upon the rest of mankind. Reflection upon these facts reveals that there are two distinct and irreducible moralities, the closed and the open.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Jacques Chevalier, Entretiens avec Bergson, pp. 75, 154–55. 159. This point is brought out again and again in the conversations between Bergson and A. D. Sertillanges collected in the latter’s little book, Avec Bergson (Paris: Librairie Gallimard, 1941), pp. 13 ff., especially p. 2O. See also “Lettre à Floris Delattre, 2 décembre, 1935” Écrits et Paroles, III, pp. 604–05.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Ibid., p. 6 (O. 985–86).

    Google Scholar 

  3. Ibid., p. 2 (O. 982): “The pressure of it, compared to that of other habits, is such that the difference in degree amounts to a difference in kind.” Bergson supports this way of classifying habits by an appeal to mathematics - “When a certain magnitude is so much greater than another that the latter is negligible in comparison, mathematicians say that it belongs to another order.” Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Frederick C. Copleston has distinguished five different senses in which Bergson uses the term obligation without seeming to be aware of it. See “Bergson on Morality,” Proceedings of the British Academy, XLI (1955), pp. 152–53 ).

    Google Scholar 

  5. The Two Sources, pp. 3–6, 74, 255–56 (O. 983–86, 1045, 1201–02).

    Google Scholar 

  6. Ibid., p. 11 (O. 99o). See also pp. 6–12 (O. 986–91). Bergson does not distinguish between a moral rule and a social convention, and in his theory of obligation there is no principle by which such a distinction could be made. See Copleston, “Bergson on Morality,” pp. 256–57.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Ibid., pp. 10–14 (O. 989–92). W. Stark questions Bergson’s claim that the individual’s compliance with obligation is for the most part automatic. Is there not rather a constant tug-of-war between individual and society, he asks? See W. Stark, “Henri Bergson: A Guide for Sociologists.” Revue Internationale de Philosophie, no. io (October, 1949 ), p. 421.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Ibid., P. 47 (O. 1021–22). See also pp. 188–89 (O. 1144–45), where Bergson in discussing the origin and function of static religion accounts for the variety of religions by showing that since religion too was intended by nature to serve a special function, godhead in general is necessary, yet the individual gods are invented by society and are, therefore, contingent.

    Google Scholar 

  9. See ibid., pp. 97–101, 106–09 (O. 1066–69, 1074–76), where Bergson discusses still another virtual instinct, the myth-making function of the intelligence which serves the same general purpose as the “totality of obligation.”

    Google Scholar 

  10. Ralph Barton Perry maintains that Bergson gives an erroneous account of the determinist position. See Present Philosophical Tendencies ( New York: Longman’s Green and Co., 1912 ). pp. 255–65.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Bergson rejects the arguments of the Determinists and the Indeterminists alike and gives an elaborate critique of both these doctrines in Time and Free Will (New York: Macmillan, 1910), pp. 140–240 (O.93–156).

    Google Scholar 

  12. The Possible and the Real, The Creative Mind, p. 123 (O. 1343).

    Google Scholar 

  13. Introduction (Part I). The Creative Mind, p. 19 (O. 1260).

    Google Scholar 

  14. Time and Free Will, pp. 125, 129, 169 (O. 83, 85, 112).

    Google Scholar 

  15. Ibid., pp. 251–52, 262–64 (O. 708–09, 717–19). See also “Life and Consciousness,” Mind-Energy, pp. 13–15 (O. 821–23).

    Google Scholar 

  16. Time and Free Will, p. 170 (O. 112).

    Google Scholar 

  17. Creative Evolution, p. 48 (O. 535).

    Google Scholar 

  18. The most remarkable thing about human freedom, according to Bergson, is its creative character; it enables man to create himself. On this topic see André Brémond, “Réflexions sur l’homme dans la philosophie de Bergson,” Archives de Philosophie, XVII, cahier I (1947). pp. 122–48, special issue entitled “Bergson et Bergsonisme.”

    Google Scholar 

  19. See Ben-Ami Sharfstein, Roots of Bergson’s Philosophy, Chapter VI, in which the author shows some marked similarities between Bergson’s conception of social morality and that of Durkheim. See also the study by J. Vialatoux, De Durkheim à Bergson (Paris: Bloud et Gay, 1939), in which the difference between Bergson’s moral philosophy and that of the sociologists s treated at length.

    Google Scholar 

  20. The Two Sources, p. 91 (O. 1060–61): “society therefore is not self-explanatory; so we must search below the social accretions, get down to Life, of which human societies, as indeed the human species altogether, are but manifestations.”

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1970 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Gallagher, I.J. (1970). The Biological Origin of Moral Obligation. In: Morality in Evolution. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-7573-7_5

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-7573-7_5

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-017-0034-4

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-015-7573-7

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics