Skip to main content
  • 87 Accesses

Abstract

Why discuss natural law, it may be asked, when the belief in the validity of this approach to ethical and political problems has suffered a marked decline, at least since the end of the eighteenth century? Why should the student of political thought be particularly interested in a discredited theory of political or moral obligation at a time when representatives of the last bastion of natural-law thinking, the Roman Catholic Church, have begun to question their church’s excessive reliance on the natural-law approach.1

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. See, for example, Gregory Baum, “Remarks on Natural Law,” The Critic, April-May 1965, vol. XXIII, no. 5, pp. 49–50;

    Google Scholar 

  2. Charles E. Curran, “Absolute norms in moral Theology” in Gene Outka and Paul Ramsey (ed.), Norm and Context in Christian Ethics, New York, 1968, ch. 5.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Carl J. Friedrich, The Philosophy of Law in Historical Perspective, Chicago, 1958, p. 178. See the literature cited there and in Guenter Lewy “Resistance to Tyranny: Treason, Right, or Duty” Western Political Quarterly, XII, 3 (Sept. 1960), pp. 581.

    Google Scholar 

  4. See Leo Strauss, Natural Right and History, University of Chicago, Chicago, 1953, and Leo Strauss and Joseph Cropsey, History of Political Philosophy, Chicago, 1963.

    Google Scholar 

  5. For an example of an attempt to relate the “laws” of biology to human conduct, see Konrad Lorenz in Life, vol. 68, no. 1 (Feb. 20, 1970), “The tragedy and magnificence of homo sapiens rise from the same smoky truth that we alone among animal species refuse to acknowledge natural law.”

    Google Scholar 

  6. On natural law as an “ideology of agreement” see Judith N. Shklar, Legalism, Cambridge, Mass., 1964, Part I. Rudolf Stammler, Theory of Justice, New York, 1925, contains his theory of “natural law with a changing content.” Jacques Maritain’s theory is best expressed in Man and the State, Chicago, 1951, while Reinhold Niebuhr’s revised version of natural law (based on the “law of love”) appears in “Christian Faith and Natural law” in George W. Forell (ed.) Christian Social Teaching, Garden City, N.Y., 1966, pp. 393–402.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Alf Ross, On Law and Justice, Berkeley, Calif., 1959, p. 261.

    Google Scholar 

  8. For examples of the three tendencies see John Courtney Murray, We Hold These Truths, New York, 1960, Part III;

    Google Scholar 

  9. Scott Buchanan, Rediscovering Natural Law, Santa Barbara, Calif., 1962;

    Google Scholar 

  10. Leo Strauss, Natural Right and History, Chicago, 1953.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Cf. John Chapman “Natural Rights and Justice in Liberalism” in D. D. Raphael (ed.); Political Theory and the Rights of Man, Bloomington, Ind., 1967, pp. 27–42.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Cf. H. L. A. Hart’s “minimum content of natural law” in The Concept of Law, Oxford, 1961, ch. 9.

    Google Scholar 

  13. John Rawls, “Distributive Justice”, in Peter Laslett and W. G. Runciman (eds.), Philosophy, Politics and Society, 3rd. series, London, 1967, pp. 58–82, has added the requirement that where inequalities exist they must be justified by their contribution to the good of all the individuals in the society.

    Google Scholar 

  14. “Essence and Concept in Natural Law Theory,” in Sidney Hook (ed.), Law and Philosophy, New York, 1964, p. 239. Green’s statement appears in his Lectures on the Principles of Political Obligation, London, 1882, reprinted 1959, pp. 32–33.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Carl Joachim Friedrich, Man and His Government, New York, 1963, pp. 38–40 and ff.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Lon Fuller, The Morality of Law, New Haven, 1964, p. 186. Davitt’s Statement is the basic argument of his monograph, The Basic Values in Law, vol. 58, part 5 (1968) of The Transactions of the American Philosophical Society, Philadelphia, 1968, p. 24.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Sidney Hook, From Hegel to Marx, paperback edition, Ann Arbor, Mich., 1962, pp. 6–7. McPherson’s statements appear in “The Maximization of Democracy” in Peter Laslett and W. G. Runciman (eds.), Philosophy, Politics, and Society (3rd series) Oxford, 1967, pp. 85, 89.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Pierre Teilhard de Chardin, “Some Reflections on the Rights of Man,” in UNESCO (ed.), Human Rights, New York, 1949, p. 106.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Klaus von Beyme

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1971 Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, Netherlands

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Sigmund, P. (1971). Natural Law Today. In: von Beyme, K. (eds) Theory and Politics / Theorie und Politik. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-1063-9_9

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-1063-9_9

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-015-0429-4

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-015-1063-9

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics