Skip to main content

Herbert Marcuse’s One-Dimensionality — The Old Style of the New Left

  • Chapter
Theory and Politics / Theorie und Politik
  • 87 Accesses

Abstract

When One-Dimensional Man first appeared in 1964 it did not cause much of a stir*. Only when student unrest broke out did the book become a bestseller, while other, earlier, publications by Marcuse were re-edited as paperbacks. The growing pressure for the reform of Academy coalesced with — as much as it was the result of — the upsurge of radical opposition to “the system” in general and to specific policies in the international arena in particular. Insofar as the militant left-wing minorities among the students succeeded in the instigation of the more violent manifestations of the student revolt in the West, the demands of reform became more radical. But this was no indication of an overriding concern of the ring-leaders with academic reforms, particularly in America.1

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. R. Nisbet, “Who Killed the Student Revolution?,” Encounter, Vol. XXXIV, February 1970, pp. 10–18.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Diana Trilling, Cambridge Review, as quoted by M. Cranston, “Herbert Marcuse,” Encounter, Vol. XXXII, March 1969, p. 46, note 10.

    Google Scholar 

  3. For a perceptive, and by no means unsympathetic, assessment of the problematical relationship between Marcuse and the students as well as the New Left in general see P. Breines, “Marcuse and the New Left in America,” in J. Habermas, (ed.), Antworten an Herbert Marcuse, Frankfurt, 1968, pp. 134–151.

    Google Scholar 

  4. See e.g., R. Steigerwald, “Ein Apostel des ‘dritten’ Weges (Zur Kritik der Theorien Herbert Marcuses),” Probleme des Friedens und des Sozialismus, Prag, 1969, Vol. XII, pp. 1095–1103. This is a mixture of misrepresentation and cogent appraisals characteristic of those who, willingly or unwillingly, labour under the pressure of toeing the Moscow-dicdated Party line.

    Google Scholar 

  5. One-Dimensional Man, Studies in the Ideology of Advanced Industrial Societies, London, 1964, p. 257. Henceforth quoted as: ODM.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Reason and Revolution, Hegel and the Rise of Social Theory, London, New York, Toronto, 1941, p. 401. Cp. also, p. 318. This book will be referred to as: RR. For Marcuse’s adherence to this view in ODM, see pp. 43, 52, 158.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Eros and Civilization, Sphere Books, London, 1969; first published in 1955. The reader will find a succinct appraisal of the main thesis of the book in Cranston’s article (see note 2 above), pp. 41–44. See also Breines, op. cit.

    Google Scholar 

  8. RR, p. 288. Cf. also, p. 320: “The economic process of capitalism exercises a totalitarian influence over all theory and practice. ‘‘

    Google Scholar 

  9. H. Marcuse, “Der Kampf gegen den Liberalismus in der totalitären Staatsauffassung,” Zeitschrift für Sozialforschung, Vol. 3, Paris, 1935, now also in English in: Negations, Penguin Press, 1968.

    Google Scholar 

  10. See Cranston, op. cit., p. 40.

    Google Scholar 

  11. RR, pp. 390, 393–4, 397–8.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Cranston, op. cit.

    Google Scholar 

  13. RR, pp. vii, 26 ff., 325 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  14. ODM, Chapters 5–7.

    Google Scholar 

  15. RR, p. 321.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Ibid., p. 218. On this and the attempt to explain the ideological motives involved in Marcuse’s apologia for Hegel’s political views, see my ‘ Revolution and Political Philosophy — Locke and Marcuse,” in M. Elliott-Bateman (ed.), The Fourth Dimension of Warfare; Part two: Violence and Politics, Manchester University Press, forthcoming.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Thus for instance in RR, p. 157, 340 passim and ODM, pp. 107 and passim, 183, 172 ff. 184 respectively.

    Google Scholar 

  18. RR, pp. 18, 37 ff., 124–7 and ODM, p. 203 passim.

    Google Scholar 

  19. RR, p. 341. For further examples of the application of the same criterion, see ODM, p. 104 and also pp. 104 ff., 193 and Chapter 7. In RR already not only capitalism but reformism, too, are totalitarian. Vide: “The idea of order, so basic to Comte’s positivism, has a totalitarian content in its social as well as methodological meaning” (p. 348).

    Google Scholar 

  20. RR, p. 338.

    Google Scholar 

  21. ODM, pp. 123 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  22. See, C. J. Friedrich (ed.), Revolution, Nomos VIII, New York, 1966, in his “Introductory Note”, p. 4

    Google Scholar 

  23. C. J. Friedrich, Man and His Government, New York — San Francisco-Toronto-London, 1963, Chapter 34 for an exhaustive treatment of the problem raised here. For my discussion of some of the aspects of the problem, see the essay mentioned in note 15 above.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Cp. H. Sée, Évolution et Révolution, Paris, 1929.

    Google Scholar 

  25. T. B. Bottomore, Critics of Society, Radical Thought in North America, London, 1967, p. 131.

    Google Scholar 

  26. ODM, p. 18.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Ibid., pp. 18, 61.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Ibid., p. 84 and passim.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Ibid., pp. 138, 87, 86, and the contexts in which these statements appear.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Ibid., p. 124.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Ibid., p.7.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Ibid., p. 72.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Ibid., p. 74.

    Google Scholar 

  34. F. E. Oppenheim, Dimensions of Freedom, New York, 1961.

    Google Scholar 

  35. ODM, p. 226.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Ibid., p. 88.

    Google Scholar 

  37. RR, p. 355.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Ibid., pp. 356, 335.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Friedrich, Man and His Government, p. 207.

    Google Scholar 

  40. ODM, p. 191.

    Google Scholar 

  41. For criticism on these lines of the reification of a class, see my forthcoming Ideology and Politics, George Allen & Unwin, London.

    Google Scholar 

  42. D. Braybrooke and C. D. Lindblom, A Strategy of Decision, Policy Evaluation as a Social Process, Glencoe — London, 1963, pp. 61 passim.

    Google Scholar 

  43. ODM, pp. 32, 50.

    Google Scholar 

  44. ODM, p. 48.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Ibid., pp. 47, 44.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Ibid., pp.88, 40, 7.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Ibid., p. 52.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Ibid., pp. 26–7. Marcuse takes the example cited in the text from Sartre who asserts that, although under the influence of machines the woman “would recall the bedroom,... it was the machine in her (sic!) which was dreaming of caresses...” (note 10, p. 27) On this Marcuse bases his conclusion that “the machine process in the technological universe breaks the innermost privacy of freedom and joins sexuality and labour in one uncons-scious, rhythmic automation — a process which parallels the assimilation of jobs” (p. 27).

    Google Scholar 

  49. Ibid., p. 194.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Ibid., p. 246.

    Google Scholar 

  51. See, e.g., V. O. Key, Jr., Public Opinion and American Democracy, New York, 1961, Chapters 15–6. Marcuse also ignores the role of those who mediate between the mass media and the members of the public as shown in E. Katz and P. F. Lazarsfeld, Personal Influence, New York, 1955.

    Google Scholar 

  52. See Friedrich’s monumental work bearing this name, especially Chapters 11 and 13.

    Google Scholar 

  53. R. A. Lane and D. O. Sears, Public Opinion, Englewood Cliffs, 2nd print., 1965, p. 53.

    Google Scholar 

  54. See above, note 15.

    Google Scholar 

  55. See my essay referred to in note 15 above.

    Google Scholar 

  56. ODM, pp. 52–3.

    Google Scholar 

  57. For Marcuse’s detailed treatment of the subject, see his Soviet Marxism, A Critical Analysis, London, 1958.

    Google Scholar 

  58. ODM, p. 4.

    Google Scholar 

  59. Habermas, op. cit., in his introduction (Zum Geleit), p. 14. 58 ODM, pp. 54, 53.

    Google Scholar 

  60. Ibid., p. 222.

    Google Scholar 

  61. See above, text to note 17.

    Google Scholar 

  62. ODM, pp. 210, 216–7.

    Google Scholar 

  63. Ibid., pp. 219–223.

    Google Scholar 

  64. Ibid., p. 219, 220.

    Google Scholar 

  65. Ibid., p. 222.

    Google Scholar 

  66. Ibid., p. 43. See also, Soviet Marxism, pp. 109 passim.

    Google Scholar 

  67. ODM, p. 42.

    Google Scholar 

  68. Ibid., pp. 44–5.

    Google Scholar 

  69. RR, p. 322.

    Google Scholar 

  70. Ibid., pp. 397, 398.

    Google Scholar 

  71. ODM, p. 44.

    Google Scholar 

  72. Loc. cit.

    Google Scholar 

  73. RR, p. 292.

    Google Scholar 

  74. Ibid., p. 293.

    Google Scholar 

  75. Ibid., pp. 321–2.

    Google Scholar 

  76. ODM, p. 240. Marcuse is obviously at fault in not making clear that his earlier and later interpretations of Marx reflect the latter’s own prevarications and that only the ‘romantic” stance remains constant. It is probably right to say that for Marx and Engels the identification of occupational specialization and slavery was almost an obsession (R. C. Tucker, Philosophy and Myth in Karl Marx, Cambridge, 1961, p. 189), despite the (fact in their futurology they could not avoid making the kind of concessions which Marcuse develops here and which can be found in the unfinished third volume of Capital (ed. by F. Engels, Chicago, 1903, pp. 954–5).

    Google Scholar 

  77. Ibid., p.44.

    Google Scholar 

  78. Ibid., p. 251.

    Google Scholar 

  79. Ibid., p. 252.

    Google Scholar 

  80. Ibid., p. 251, My italics.

    Google Scholar 

  81. Ibid., p. 252.

    Google Scholar 

  82. Ibid., p. 235.

    Google Scholar 

  83. E. Gellner, Thought and Change, London 1964, p. 118.

    Google Scholar 

  84. ODM, p. 126.

    Google Scholar 

  85. Ibid., p. 231.

    Google Scholar 

  86. Aristotle, Metaphysics, Book 1, 982 b.

    Google Scholar 

  87. Cp. Cranston, loc. cit., p. 50.

    Google Scholar 

  88. ODM, p. 60, Cp. also pp. 62, 249.

    Google Scholar 

  89. See above, text following notes 31 and 46.

    Google Scholar 

  90. ODM, p. 73.

    Google Scholar 

  91. Ibid., p. 74.

    Google Scholar 

  92. Ibid., p. 242.

    Google Scholar 

  93. In Reason and Revolution, Marcuse had said: “Today, when all the technical potentialities for an abundant life are at hand, the National Socialists ‘consider the decline of the standard of living inevitable’ and indulge in panegyrics on impoverishment” (p. 415).

    Google Scholar 

  94. ODM, p. 244.

    Google Scholar 

  95. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  96. M. Rokeach, The Open and the Closed Mind, Investigations into the Nature of Belief Systems and Personality Systems, New York, 1960.

    Google Scholar 

  97. ODM, p. 220.

    Google Scholar 

  98. Ibid., pp. 6, 9 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  99. Ibid., p. 250.

    Google Scholar 

  100. Ibid., pp. 39–40.

    Google Scholar 

  101. J. L. Talmon, The Origins of Totalitarian Democracy, London, 1952 and Political Messianism, The Romantic Phase, London, 1960.

    Google Scholar 

  102. A. MacIntyre, Marcuse, Fontana/Collins, London, 1970, concludes his study with the words: “.. .Marcuse has produced a theory that, like so many of its predecessors, invokes the great names of freedom and reason while betraying their substance at every important point” (p. 92).

    Google Scholar 

  103. See above, note 15.

    Google Scholar 

  104. Just as to-day the conditions of the affluent society require the “educational dictatorship”, so in 1941 did the view of the widening gap between the impoverishment of the worker and the wealth he produces (RR, p. 274) provide “the final basis for the universal character of the communist revolution” (p. 291).

    Google Scholar 

  105. K. Kautsky, The Dictatorship of the Proletariat, first edition in German in 1918; paperback ed., Ann Arbor, 1964.

    Google Scholar 

  106. S. Avineri, The Social and Political Thought of Karl Marx, Cambridge, 1968, pp. 216–8.

    Google Scholar 

  107. Cp. for instance, Habermas, op. cit., in his introduction and especially the contribution by A. Schmidt, “Existential-Ontologie und historischer Materialismus bei Herbert Marcuse”, ibid., pp. 17–49, who like MacIntyre stresses Marcuse’s deviations from Marxian tenets. However, unlike Maclntyre, with whose evaluation I find myself in far-going agreement, Schmidt takes an on the whole appreciative view of Marcuse’s achievments. Nevertheless, Schmidt (like other contributors to Habermas’ volume) seems to me to proceed from a position which is nearer to that underlying Steigerwald’s negative judgment (see above, note 3) than that which informs MacIntyre’s unsparing critique.

    Google Scholar 

  108. B. Croce, History as the Story of Liberty, London, 1941, p. 244.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Klaus von Beyme

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1971 Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, Netherlands

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Seliger, M. (1971). Herbert Marcuse’s One-Dimensionality — The Old Style of the New Left. In: von Beyme, K. (eds) Theory and Politics / Theorie und Politik. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-1063-9_10

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-1063-9_10

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-015-0429-4

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-015-1063-9

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics