Skip to main content

The Intention of Consequence

  • Chapter
  • 125 Accesses

Abstract

Besides simple apprehension and judgment there is a third operation of reason belonging to the intellective power, not as intellect, but properly as reason. This is discursive reasoning.1 It is described as the motion of the intellect passing from one thing known or considered to another:

Ratiocinativa est nostra consideratio quando ab uno considerato in aliud transimus. ... Ratiocinatio autem est quidam motus intellectus transeuntis ab uno in aliud.2

Ratiocinari autem proprie est devenire ex uno in cognitionem alterius.3

Est enim actus rationis quasi quidam motus de uno in alterum perveniens.4

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   79.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Bibliography

  • Alamannus (under G), Q. XX, “De syllogismo”; Q. XXI, “De syllogismo demonstrativo”; QQ. XXII-XXVII, on demonstration.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baumgaertner, William, “The Nature of Induction,” Proceedings of the Am. Cath. Phil. Assn., XXV (1951), 130–136.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernard, Rogat., O.P. “Proprium rationis est discurrere,” Xenia Thomistica, 2 vols., ed. by H. S. Szabó, O.P. Rome: Vatican Polyglot Press, 1925. I, 147–157.

    Google Scholar 

  • Conway, Pierre, O.P. “Induction in Aristotle and St. Thomas,” The Thomist, XXII (1959), 336–365.

    Google Scholar 

  • Demers, G. Ed. “Les divers sens du mot ratio au moyen-âge,” Etudes d’histoire littéraire et doctrinale du XIIIe siècle. Ottawa: Inst. d’Et. Méd., and Paris: Vrin, 1932. I, 105–139.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dolan, S. Edmund, F.S.C. “Resolution and Composition in Speculative and Practical Discourse,” Laval théol. et phil., VI (1950), 9–62.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guérard des Lauriers, MX., O.P. “L’induction,” Les sciences philosophiques et théologiques, 1941-42, pp. 5-27.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hawkins, D. J. B., Causality and Implication. London: Sheed & Ward, 1937.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoenen, P., S.J. “De origine primorum principiorum scientiae,” Gregorianum, XIV (1933), 153–184.

    Google Scholar 

  • Isaac, J., O.P. “La notion de la dialectique” (under chap. II).

    Google Scholar 

  • — “Sur la connaissance de la vérité” (under chap. VIII).

    Google Scholar 

  • John of St. Thomas (under G), P. I, Lib. III; Quaestiones Disputandae, Q. 8; P. II, QQ. 24 & 25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lachance. “St. Thomas dans l’histoire de la logique” (under F).

    Google Scholar 

  • Le Blond (under chap. II).

    Google Scholar 

  • Llambias, H. “Ser y devenir en logica,” Sapientia, VII (1952), 90–102.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maritain, Jacques. “La vraie notion du syllogisme,” Rev. de Philosophie, XXX (19230, 174-181).

    Google Scholar 

  • Parker and Veatch (under G), Part III, “The Argument.”

    Google Scholar 

  • Péghaire, Julien, C.S. Sp. Intellectus et Ratio selon saint Thomas d’Aquin. Ottawa: Inst. d’Et. Méd., and Paris: Vrin, 1936. Deuxième partie, pp. 73-169.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pegis, Anton C. “In Umbra Intelligentiae,” The New Scholasticism, XIV (1940), 146–180, esp. Part. II.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pétrin (under chap. VIII).

    Google Scholar 

  • Phelan (under chap. VIII).

    Google Scholar 

  • Régis, L. M., O.P. “Analyse et synthèse dans l’oeuvre de saint Thomas,” in Studia Mediaevalia in honorem A.R.P. Raymundi J. Martin, O.P. Bruges: De Tempel, 1948. Pp. 303–330.

    Google Scholar 

  • Epistemology (under chap. V), Part IV, esp. chap. XII, “Infallible Knowledge of Mediate Truth.”

    Google Scholar 

  • L’opinion (under chap. II).

    Google Scholar 

  • Richard, T., O.P. Philosophie du raisonnement dans la science d’après saint Thomas. Paris: Bonne Presse, 1919.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schorsch, Alexander. “Scientific Induction,” Proceedings of the Am. Cath. Phil. Assn., XXV (1951), 136–141.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, Gerard, S. J. “Before You Start Talking about God,” The Modern Schoolman, XXIII (1945-46), 24–43.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Tonquédec. Critique de la connaissance (under G), chaps. VIII-XI, “Les inférences.”

    Google Scholar 

  • Trépanier, E. “La connaissance des premiers principes: une interprétation,” Laval théol. et phil., IV (1948), 289–310.

    Google Scholar 

  • Veatch. Intentional Logic (under G), chap. 6, “Argument,” A, I-III.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yon, A. “Ratio et les mots de la famille de reor,” in Contributions à l’étude historique du vocabulaire latin. Paris: Champion, 1933.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1966 Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, Netherlands

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Schmidt, R.W. (1966). The Intention of Consequence. In: The Domain of Logic According to Saint Thomas Aquinas. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-0939-8_9

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-0939-8_9

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-015-0367-9

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-015-0939-8

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics