Skip to main content

Complementarity and the Scientific Method: A Criticism

  • Chapter
  • 235 Accesses

Abstract

The definition of quantum mechanical variables can only be made with the aid of classical physical concepts. These are identical — except for refinements — with the concepts of everyday life. Heisenberg has written: “The concepts of classical physics will remain the basis of any exact and objective science. Because we demand of the results of science that they can be objectively proved (i. e. by measurements, registered on suitable apparatus) we are forced to express these results in the language of classical physics... Thus while the laws of classical physics... appear only as limiting cases of more general and abstract connections, the concepts associated with these laws remain an indispensable part of the language of science without which it would not be possible even to speak of scientific results” 1.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Heisenberg, Philosophic Problems etc., p. 45; the same idea is expressed in the same author’s Physics and Philosophy (New York: Harper, 1958), pp. 44, 144. sophical outlooks of relativists and quantum theorists, see E. Wigner, “Relativistic Invariance and Quantum Phenomena”, Rev. Mod. Phys., xxix (1959), pp. 255–268.

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  2. P. Suppes, “Probability Concepts in Quantum Mechanics”, Phil. Sci., xxviii (1961), pp. 378–389

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. H. Margenau, “Measurements and Quantum States”, Phil. Sci., xxx (1963), pp. 138–157.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. A pure case (reiner Fall) or a pure state is one representable by a ray in Hilbert space; statistically it means that it is impossible to produce it by combining statistical ensembles with different characteristics. The term was introduced by H. Weyl and used by Heisenberg and von Neumann. Cf., H. Weyl, Theory of Groups etc., p. 75; J. von Neumann, Mathematical Foundations etc., pp. 306-307, 328-329; Heisenberg, Physical Principles etc., p. 56. The difference between a pure case and a mixture has been studied by E. P. Wigner in “The Problem of Measurement”, Am. Jour Phys., xxxi (1963), p. 6, and by

    Article  MathSciNet  ADS  Google Scholar 

  5. H. Margenau, Phil. Sci., xxx (1963), pp. 138–157.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. E. P. Wigner, Am. Jour. Phys., xxxi (1963), p. 6.

    Article  MathSciNet  ADS  Google Scholar 

  7. F. London and E. Bauer, La théorie de l’observation en mécanique quantique (Paris: Hermann, 1939).

    Google Scholar 

  8. Among those physicists who reject the Projection Postulate are, Margenau, Lande, Feyerabend, Schrödinger. Cf. H. Margenau, Phil. Sci., xxx (1963), 1–16, 138-157; P. K. Feyerabend, Frontiers of Science and Philosophy; A. Landé, From Dualism to Unity in Quantum Mechanics (Cambridge: 1960)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  9. E. Schrödinger, Naturwiss., XXIII (1935), p. 812.

    Google Scholar 

  10. London and Bauer, loc. cit. pp. 48-51; also D. Bohm, Quantum Theory (New York: Prentice-Hall, 1951); G. Ludwig, Die Grundlagen der Quantenmechanik (Berlin: 1954); P. K. Feyerabend, Observation and Interpretation (London: 1957)

    Google Scholar 

  11. A. Daneri, A. Loinger, G. M. Prosperi, Nucl. Phys., XXXIII (1962), p. 297.

    MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  12. Recent studies have shown that the size of the apparatus is of considerable importance to the measurement. E. Wigner and H. Salecker showed the necessity of relatively massive apparatus for the precise determination of time (Phys. Rev., cix, 1958, p. 571); for the influence of the size of the apparatus on the accuracy of measurements, cf., E. Wigner, Zeit f. Physik, cxxxi (1952) p. 101; Amer. Jour. Phys., xxxi (1963), p. 6

    ADS  Google Scholar 

  13. H. Araki and M. Yanase, “Measurement of Quantum Mechanical Operators”, Phys. Rev., cxx (1960), pp. 622–626

    Article  MathSciNet  Google Scholar 

  14. M. Yanase, “Optimal Measuring Apparatus”, Phys. Rev., cxxiii (1961), pp. 666–668. Wigner concludes: “This raises the suspicion that the macroscopic nature of the apparatus is necessary in principle” (Am. Jour. Phys., xxxi, 1963, p. 6).

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1965 Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, Netherlands

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Heelan, P.A. (1965). Complementarity and the Scientific Method: A Criticism. In: Quantum Mechanics and Objectivity. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-0831-5_4

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-0831-5_4

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-015-0300-6

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-015-0831-5

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics