Skip to main content

Abstract

In trying to understand what human beings are and what they do, one of the most fundamental and useful distinctions is between things which happen to us and things which happen because of us, between what we do and what is done to us, between ourselves as agents and ourselves as patients. A third distinction is also sometimes required. Sometimes we need to think of ourselves as transeunt or intermediate causes, as links in an extended chain of causes and effects which originates before us, passes through us, and ends beyond us. Many philosophers of deterministic persuasion have attempted to erode away the concept of agency by insisting that all that men do and all that they are can be explained as the consequence of causal conditions which lie ultimately in our heredity and environment and which have operated upon us and within us to make us exactly what we are and to make us do exactly what we do, so that in the final analysis all that you or I do is merely the outcome of that which is done to us. Determinists want to insist that at best we are only transeunt causes.1

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Hastings Rashdall wrote, for example, that “Actions are the necessary result of original character and environment. Original character and environment being the same, the act could not have been different.” Hastings Rashdall, The Theory of Good and Evil, (Oxford, University Press, 1938), vol. II, p. 303.

    Google Scholar 

  2. For a superb discussion of attention which is quite different in approach from what follows here, and yet which in my opinion largely complements the position which I develop, see the essay by U. T. Place, “The Concept of Heed,” British Journal of Psychology, XLV, No. 4, 1954, pp. 243–255.

    Google Scholar 

  3. C. A. Campbell, On Selfhood and Godhood (London, George Allen and Unwin, Ltd, 1957), p. 144.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Margaret Knight, William James, (Harmondsworth, Penguin Books, Ltd., 1954), pp. 172–173.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Ibid., p. 111. I think James was more accurate here than R. G. Collingwood who seemed to believe that all attending was completely active. See: R. G. Collingwood, The Principles of Art (New York, Oxford University Press, 1958), p. 208.

    Google Scholar 

  6. W. D. Ross, The Right and the Good (Oxford, The Clarendon Press, 1930), p. 158.

    Google Scholar 

  7. C. A. Campbell, “The Psychology of Effort of Will,” Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, Vol. XL (1939–40), p. 50.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1969 Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, Netherlands

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Edwards, R.B. (1969). Agency, Attention, and Choice. In: Freedom, Responsibility and Obligation. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-0643-4_2

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-0643-4_2

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-015-0154-5

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-015-0643-4

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics