Skip to main content

Benedetto Croce as a Foil to R. G. Collingwood

  • Chapter
The Formative Years of R. G. Collingwood
  • 63 Accesses

Abstract

Benedetto Croce is the contemporary thinker whom early Collingwood most resembles. As we shall see, this is true especially of Croce’s writings from 1901 to 1910. Whether the resemblance is owing to Croce’s direct influence upon Collingwood or to Vico’s influence upon both Croce and Collingwood 1 is one of those problems of affiliation which are so elusive in the case of Collingwood (and also of Croce). That Collingwood felt a certain affinity with Croce is abundantly clear. In 1921, for example, Collingwood wrote to Croce:

This I say because some things in the paper look like the observations of a hostile critic, and I should like you to know that that is very far from being the character they were intended to bear. I have no time to write about work to which I feel hostile: I only write about the people whom I most closely agree with.2

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. On Collingwood and Vico, see infra, Ch. VIII, notes 29-31.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Letter by R. G. Collingwood to Benedetto Croce, Oxford, May 28, 1921. Quoted in Donagan, The Later Philosophy of R. G. Collingwood, p. 314. The paper referred to is “Croce’s Philosophy of History,” Hibbert Journal, 19, (1920–1921), 263-278.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Collingwood’s translations from Croce include: The Philosophy of Giambattista Vico (London, 1913); An Autobiography (Oxford, 1927) from Contributato alla Critica di me stesso (Bari, 1915); and “Aesthetic”, in The Encyclopaedia Britannica, 14th ed. (Chicago, 1929), Vol. I, pp. 263-271.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Collingwood’s translations from de Ruggiero include: Modern Philosophy, tr. R. G. Collingwood with Howard Hannay (London, 1921) from Part IV of the Ruggiero’s Storia delta filosofia; and A History of Modern Liberalism (London, 1927).

    Google Scholar 

  5. See infra, Ch. VIII, Sect. 1.

    Google Scholar 

  6. There are one or two lapses, however, In The Idea of History, p. 194, Collingwood cites the 1909 edition of Croce’s Logica as if he thought it were the only edition. Actually the first edition came out in 1904 and was radically revised in 1909.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Quoted in Donagan, The Later Philosophy of R. G. Collingwood, p. 316.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Collingwood’s other monographs include: “Croce’s Philosophy of History”, (1921), in Debbins ed., pp. 3-22; “Plato’s Philosophy of Art”, (1925) in Donagan, ed., pp. 157-183; “Oswald Spengler and the Theory of Historical Cycles”, (1927) in Debbins, ed., pp. 57-75.

    Google Scholar 

  9. For more details on Croce’s early periods, see infra Ch. VII, Sect. 3. The best account of them is perhaps still Croce’s Contributato alla critica di me stesso, which Collingwood translated in 1927 under the title An Autobiography [cited hereafter as Croce, An Autobiography]. As translator, Collingwood may have borrowed this title from John Stuart Mill’s (1806–1873) Autobiography, (1873), or, as seems more likely, from Giambattista Vico’s Auto-biografia (1728-29, with an appendix, 1818). It is evidence of Collingwood’s affinity with Croce that he chose to use the same title for his own An Autobiography (1938), a work which resembles Croce’s in the emphasis that both works place on expounding the author’s doctrine rather than narrating the events of a lifetime.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Dora Marra, Conversazioni con Benedetto Croce su alcuni libri della su Biblioteca (Milan, 1952).

    Google Scholar 

  11. Quoted in: Francesco Olgiati, Benedetto Croce e lo Storicismo, (Milan, 1953), p. 11.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Croce, An Autobiography, pp. 26-27, 60.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Speculum Mentis (1924), p. 12, Collingwood, Outlines of a Philosophy of Art (1925) in Donagan, ed., p. 153; Collingwood, The Principles of Art (1928), p. 3.

    Google Scholar 

  14. On Gentile, see infra, Ch. VIII, Sect. 2.

    Google Scholar 

  15. The Idea of History, p. 159.

    Google Scholar 

  16. The passages in The Idea of History are as follows: on Kant, pp. 93-104; on Hegel, pp. 113-122; on Croce, pp. 190-204; on Oakeshott, pp. 151-159.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Oakeshott, Experience and Its Modes (Cambridge, 1933), p. 6. In the Preface, p. v, Oakeshott expresses appreciation for the “kindness and encouragement” of H. H. Joachim (1868–1938), who was a friend and colleague of Collingwood at Oxford. Collingwood mentions Joachim as “an intimate and beloved friend of my own” in An Autobiography, p. 18.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Tomlin, “The Philosophy of R. G. Collingwood”, Ratio, 1 (1958), 124.

    Google Scholar 

  19. See Oakeshott, Rationalism in Politics (London, 1962). One parallel, however, remains: Oakeshott shares Collingwood’s admiration for Hobbes as a giant among political theorists. See Oakeshott “Introduction”, in Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, (Oxford, 1960), pp. vii-lxvi, and Collingwood, The New Leviathan, pp. iii-iv.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Croce, An Autobiography, pp. 28-31.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Croce, An Autobiography, p. 26.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Croce, An Autobiography, pp. 34-35.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Croce, An Autobiography, p. 42. Croce did not hear Labriola’s lectures on the philosophy of history, which give an interesting view of the state of the field before Croce tackled it. See Antonio Labriola, I Problemi delta Filosofia delta Storia. Prelezione letta nella Università di Roma it 28 febbraio 1887 (Turin, 1887).

    Google Scholar 

  24. Croce, La Storia ridotta sotto il concetto generale dell’Arte (1893).

    Google Scholar 

  25. Labriola’s La Concezione Materialistica delta Storia (Rome, 1895–1896) prompted Croce to take up the study of Marx. Alfred Bonnet translated the work, with a Preface by Georges Sorel, as Essais sur la conception matérialiste de l’histoire (Paris, 1898).

    Google Scholar 

  26. Materialismo storico ed Economia marxistica (Milan, 1900); tr. C. M. Meredith, Historical Materialism and the Economics of Karl Marx (London, 1914).

    Google Scholar 

  27. See R. G. Collingwood, “Economics as a Philosophical Science”, International Journal of Ethics, 36 (1925–1926), 162–185. This article attempts to define “economic action” as a “subordinate element” in moral action. The basic concepts bear a striking resemblance to Croce in the Pratica, which Collingwood cites, ibid., p. 163, note 1. Marx is not mentioned. For Collingwood’s attitude toward Marx as an unconvincing philosopher, but a “grand fighter”, see Collingwood, An Autobiography, p. 152.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Jules Chaix-Ruy, “La Genèse de l’historicisme chez Benedetto Croce”, Revue internationale de philosophie, 7 (1953), 315.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Croce, An Autobiography, p. 27.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Between 1902 and 1912, Croce revised his Estetica no fewer than three times, making a total of four editions in ten years. Similarly the Logica went through two radically different versions, between 1905 and 1909, and the Pratica had seen its third edition by 1916, just eight years after it was first published. For a complete list of the various editions see infra, Bibliography.

    Google Scholar 

  31. For Collingwood’s views on religion as a distinct form of experience, see infra, Ch. X, Sect. 2.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Tr. as What is Living and What is Dead in the Philosophy of Hegel, tr. from 3 Ital. ed. of 1912 by Douglas Ainslie (London, 1915) Ainslie took as his title the longest essay in the Saggio: Ciò che è vivo e ciò che è morto nella filosofia di Hegel”. (1906.)

    Google Scholar 

  33. See infra, Ch IX, Sect. 1. For the phrase, “distinct but not separate”, see Speculum Mentis, p 170

    Google Scholar 

  34. Croce, The Philosophy of Giambattista Vico, tr. R. G. Collingwood, p. 236.

    Google Scholar 

  35. First published as articles in 1912–1913. It appeared in book form first in a German edition, Zur Theorie und Geschichte der Historiographie (Tübingen, 1915). The first Italian edition came out in 1917. It is this work which Collingwood discusses in “Croce’s Philosophy of History”, Hibbert Journal, 19 (1920–1921), 263-278; repr. in Debbins, ed., pp. 3-22. Croce himself considered the Storiografia as the fourth and concluding volume in his Filosofia dello Spirito.

    Google Scholar 

  36. For a correction of this view, see infra, Ch. VIII, note 2, and Ch. XII, Sect. 1.

    Google Scholar 

  37. In Croce’s case, historicism is best understood to mean the thesis that history and philosophy are co-extensive. This position of Croce’s is most widely known today in the form in which it is stated in Storia come Pensiero e come Azione (1938); tr. Sylvia Sprigge as History as the Story of Liberty (New York, 1938).

    Google Scholar 

  38. For Gentile’s contribution to the philosophy of culture and Collingwood’s appraisal of it, see infra, Ch. VIII, Sect. 2.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Collingwood, “Can the New Idealism Dispense with Mysticism?” PAS, Supp. 3 (1923), 162.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Collingwood, Letter to Croce of May 29, 1921, quoted in Donagan, The Later Philosophy of R. G. Collingwood, p. 314.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Anyone familiar with Speculum Mentis need only browse through Croce’s Estetica, Logica, and Pratica to be amazed by the similarity in terminology. At times, if one judges merely by the terminology and not by the argument, one might think that Speculum Mentis was a later work by the same author.

    Google Scholar 

  42. As an undergraduate at Exeter College, Oxford, Ainslie took a Pass in English History and French literature in 1887.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Bernard Bosanquet, Review of Benedetto Croce, Philosophy of the Practical: Economic and Ethic, tr., Douglas Ainslie (London, MacMillan, 1913) in: The Hibbert Journal, 13, (1914–15), 217-220; Review of Croce, Logic as the Science of the Pure Concept, tr., Douglas Ainslie from the 3rd Italian ed., (London, MacMillan, 1917) in: Mind 27 (1918), 475-484.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Ibid., p. 475, note 1.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Smith published a total of twenty articles and no books.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Collingwood, An Autobiography, p. 18.

    Google Scholar 

  47. J. A. Smith, “Philosophy as the Development of the Notion and Reality of Self-Consciousness”, in J. H. Muirhead, ed., Contemporary British Philosophy: Personal Statements, 2nd Series (London, 1925), pp. 227–244, esp. 231-233.

    Google Scholar 

  48. J. A. Smith, “Knowing and Acting”, [26 November 1910] in: Oxford Lectures in Philosophy 1910–1923 (Oxford, 1910–1923), pp. 3–31.

    Google Scholar 

  49. It appeared in 1913 along with an English translation of one other of Croce’s works: The Philosophy of the Practical, tr. Douglas Ainslie (London, 1913); one year later appeared Historical Materialism and the Economics of Karl Marx, tr. C. M. Meredith (London, 1914). Together with Ainslie’s translation of the Aesthetic (London, 1909), Collingwood’s Vico brought to four the number of Croce’s works available in English by 1914. For further translations in 1915 and after, see Bibliography.

    Google Scholar 

  50. For Carritt’s reminiscences of Oxford philosophy of the 1890’s, see: “Our Fathers that Begot Us”, Oxford Magazine, 77, (1958–1959), 366-370, and “Fifty Years a Don”, Oxford Magazine, 78, (1959–1960), 274-276.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Collingwood, An Autobiography, p. 22.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Collingwood, An Autobiography, p. 56.

    Google Scholar 

  53. E. F. Carritt, The Theory of Beauty (London, 1914), pp. 179–218.

    Google Scholar 

  54. Collingwood, An Autobiography, p. 56.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Collingwood was to share this view. See Outlines of a Philosophy of Art in Donagan, ed., pp. 120-121, on the way in which “formalistic art” and “traditions of design” are perpetuated by “schools” of artists.

    Google Scholar 

  56. See infra, Ch. X, Sect. 1. See also Collingwood, Outlines of a Philosophy of Art (1925) in Donagan, ed., pp. 52-55. Cf. ibid., p. 88: “The Aesthetic activity is the activity of imagination and imagination creates its own object.” See also The Principles of Art, Ch. 7.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Collingwood, Outlines of a Philosophy of Art in Donagan, ed., p. 154.

    Google Scholar 

  58. See especially Outlines of a Philosophy of Art, in Donagan, ed., Ch. II, “The Forms of Beauty”, pp.72-89.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1967 Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, Netherlands

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Johnston, W.M. (1967). Benedetto Croce as a Foil to R. G. Collingwood. In: The Formative Years of R. G. Collingwood. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-9481-5_7

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-9481-5_7

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-011-8678-0

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-011-9481-5

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics