Skip to main content

The Concept of Variability among the Secondary Precepts of Natural Law

  • Chapter
Book cover Primary and Secondary Precepts in Thomistic Natural Law Teaching

Abstract

As we noted in our opening chapter, there was considerable difference of opinion over the kind of variability which could be attributed to natural law. Before analysing the different forms of variability, it is necessary that we state in very general terms what we mean by this word. While we will, in the course of our discussion, be interested in any form of variability which may be relevant to natural law, it is the following kind which will interest us most. We wish to discover whether a certain precept may on one occasion be in accord with natural law and yet not be so on another occasion. In other words, we are asking whether it could ever be correct to say of a certain action X (defined by precept a) that to have performed it in the past (perhaps ten years or perhaps a century before) would have been to act in accordance with natural law, but to perform it at this moment would be contrary to natural law. This we submit is a field of investigation which has never been adequately considered. In our opening chapter we saw that very few writers were in complete agreement as to what form of variability could be attributed to natural law. It is the nature of the variability that we hope to clarify in this present chapter. Here and there we will give examples to illustrate a particular point, but these must be regarded as incidental to our main discussion. What we are interested in is not so much which precepts of natural law may be regarded as variable, but rather, whether it is meaningful to speak of variability at all, and (if it is) to ascertain the reasons why such variability may occur.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Ia IIae, q. 58, a. 5.

    Google Scholar 

  2. IIa IIae, q. 47, a. 15.

    Google Scholar 

  3. A. D. Sertillanges, La philosophie morale de Saint Thomas d’Aquin, 9th ed. Paris, 1961, p. 112: “la mesure de leur variabilité sera celle de leur éloignement par rapport au thème général que doit réaliser la fonction.”

    Google Scholar 

  4. M. Cronin, The Science of Ethics, I, Dublin, 1909, p. 611: “What is necessary for the satisfaction of an appetite under one set of circumstances may not be necessary under another.”

    Google Scholar 

  5. A. D. Sertillanges, op. cit., p. III: “II s’ensuivra que dans certains cas, cela ne sera plus à faire qui, envisagé en général, paraissait évidemment juste, et que, subjectivement, cela pourra ne paraÎtre point juste qui est cependant à faire.”

    Google Scholar 

  6. R. Jolivet, Traité de philosophie, IV, Morale, Paris, 1962, p. 117.

    Google Scholar 

  7. H. Rommen, The Natural Law, London, 1947, pp. 224–225. On this same point see also, René Simon, Morale, Paris, 1961, pp. 186-187. He describes this present issue as one of “apparent variability”.

    Google Scholar 

  8. O. Lottin, Morale Fondamentale, Paris, 1954, pp. 179–180.

    Google Scholar 

  9. R.Jolivet, op. cit., pp. 119-121.

    Google Scholar 

  10. R.Jolivet, op. cit., pp. 119-121.

    Google Scholar 

  11. O. Lottin, op. cit., p. 180.

    Google Scholar 

  12. P. M. Van Overbeke, “La loi naturelle et le droit naturel selon S. Thomas,” Revue Thomiste, 57 (1957), p. 470.

    Google Scholar 

  13. J. Fuchs, Le droit naturel, Tournai, 1960, p. 54. See also, Theologia Moralis Generalis, Pars Prima, Rome, 1960, pp. 66-68.

    Google Scholar 

  14. R. Simon, Morale, pp. 184-187.

    Google Scholar 

  15. L. Oeing-Hanhoff, “Thomas von Aquin und die Situation des Thomismus heute,” Philosophisches Jahrbuch, 70 (1962), pp. 17–33.

    Google Scholar 

  16. G. Fay, “Human Evolution: A Challenge to Thomistic Ethics,” International Philosophical Quarterly, 2 (1962), pp. 50–80. See also, “Towards a Thomistic-Anthropological View of the Evolution of Obligation,” N.L. For., 7 (1962), pp. 38-53.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Ia IIae, q. 77, a. 2. cf. Ia IIae, q. 17, a. 2.

    Google Scholar 

  18. B. M. Crowe, “Human Nature — Immutable or Mutable?” I.T.Q., 30 (1963), p. 208.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Ia IIae, q. 94, a. 4, q. 58, a. 5; Ia Pars, q. 113, a. 1.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Ibid. cf. M. B. Crowe, op. cit., p. 208 f.n. 16. He points out that Caesar, although critical of the morals of the Germans, was not quite as hard on them as S. Thomas assumes. To substantiate this point he cites the exact words of Caesar: “latrocinia nullam habet infamiam quae extra fines cuiusque civitatis fiunt, atque ea iuventutis exercendae ac desidiae minuendae causa fieri praedicant…”

    Google Scholar 

  21. Ia IIae, q. 99, a. 2, ad 2. cf. Suppl., q. 54, a. 3, ad 2; where this point is repeated: “That certain barbarians are united carnally to their parents does not come from the natural law but from the passion of concupiscence which has clouded the natural law in them.”

    Google Scholar 

  22. It is necessary to distinguish between the difference of moral belief, due to the over-influence of the passions, and due to a genuine instance of intellectual difficulty. Often the dividing line between these two cases is not clear. The notion of genuine intellectual difficulty and the suggested variability associated with this will be considered in section IV.

    Google Scholar 

  23. IIa IIae, q. 47, a. 15; cf. S. Deploige, The Conflict Between Ethics and Sociology, (trans. C. C. Miltner), London, 1938, p. 320: “Morality varies necessarily from one group to another according to their degree of civilization.”

    Google Scholar 

  24. In Politic, II, 12, cited by S. Deploige, op. cit., p. 321.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Ia IIae, q. 94, a. 5.

    Google Scholar 

  26. See above pp. 93-97 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  27. cf. Ia IIae, q. 94, a. 5, ad 1: “The written law (human law) is said to be given for the correction of the natural law, either because it supplies what was wanting to the natural law; or because the natural law was perverted in the hearts of some men, as to certain matters, so that they esteemed those things good which are naturally evil; which perversion stood in need of correction.”

    Google Scholar 

  28. J. Maritain, On the Philosophy of History, London, 1959, pp. 82–84.

    Google Scholar 

  29. J. Maritain, loc. cit., p. 82.

    Google Scholar 

  30. J. Maritain, loc. cit., pp. 82-83; cf. G. Renard, Le Droit, Vordre et la Raison, Paris, 1927, p. 23, 29 and 120.

    Google Scholar 

  31. J. Maritain, op. cit., pp. 82-83.

    Google Scholar 

  32. J. Maritain, op. cit., p. 83: “For many, many centuries, and even Christian centuries, it was considered quite normal to kill prisoners of war. No difference was recognised between an enemy soldier in combat and one who had been taken prisoner … But now we have a completely different view of our obligations towards prisoners of war.”

    Google Scholar 

  33. W. L. Shirer, The Rise and Fall of the Third Reich, London., 1962, p. 945.

    Google Scholar 

  34. J. Maritain, op. cit., p. 84.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Often the distinction between these two suggested reasons is a confused one. For some precepts, it is difficult to ascertain whether their apparent change is due to the influence of the passions or to an insufficiently developed understanding of the nature of man. For convenience, we have separated these two reasons, but it is perfectly possible that they may both influence us in our formulation of a precept.

    Google Scholar 

  36. It is important that we distinguish between the change in natural law as considered in this section brought about by the development in our understanding, and the change we will be discussing in section VII brought about by a change in the intrinsic structure of society.

    Google Scholar 

  37. A. D. Sertillanges, La philosophie morale de Saint Thomas d’Aquin, p. 112.

    Google Scholar 

  38. H. Rommen, The Natural Law, S. Louis, Mo., 1947, p. 181, f.n.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Ia IIae, q. 100, a. 1.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Ia IIae, q. 100, a. 1.

    Google Scholar 

  41. M. Cronin, The Science of Ethics, I, Dublin, 1909, p. 611.

    Google Scholar 

  42. A. D. Sertillanges, La philosophie morale de Saint Thomas d’Aquin, Paris, 1961, p. 107.

    Google Scholar 

  43. A. D. Sertillanges, op. cit., p. 111.

    Google Scholar 

  44. R. Jolivet, Traité de philosophie morale, t. IV, Morale, 6th ed., Paris, 1962, p. 117.

    Google Scholar 

  45. For a discussion concerning the apparent variability involved in the precept, “killing ought to be avoided,” see, J. Fuchs, Theologia Moralis Generalis, Pars Prima, Rome, 1960, pp. 81-82. cf. L. Bender, Philosophia iuris, 2nd ed., Rome, 1955, pp. 185-186, cited by M. B. Crowe, “Human Nature — Immutable or Mutable?,” I.T.Q., 30 (1963), p. 229.

    Google Scholar 

  46. O. Lottin, “La Valeur des formules de S. Thomas d’Aquin concernant la loi naturelle,” Mélanges Joseph Maréchal, II, Bruxelles, 1950, pp. 370–372.

    Google Scholar 

  47. H. Rommen, The Natural Law, trans. T. R. Hanley, S. Louis, Mo., 1947, pp. 224–225.

    Google Scholar 

  48. A. Van Hove, Prologomena ad Codicem Juris Canonici, Malines-Rome, 1945, n. 55 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  49. M. B. Crowe, “Human Nature—Immutable or Mutable?,” I.T.Q., 30 (1963), pp. 209–211, 226.

    Google Scholar 

  50. J. Rickaby, Oxford and Cambridge Conferences, 2nd series, London, 1902, pp. 17–19.

    Google Scholar 

  51. J. Fuchs, Theologia Moralis Generalis, Pars Prima, Rome, 1960, pp. 66–88.

    Google Scholar 

  52. J. Fuchs, op. cit., p. 68.

    Google Scholar 

  53. R. Jolivet, op. cit., pp. 119-123.

    Google Scholar 

  54. Ia IIae, q. 94, a. 4. For further references to this example, see below, p. 165, f.n. 1.

    Google Scholar 

  55. IIa IIae, q. 66, a. 6, ad 1: cf. ibid., a. 7.

    Google Scholar 

  56. We note that the example concerned with the repayment of debts (or deposited goods) is to be found first in Bk. 1 of Plato’s Republic. As well as the reference we will be referring to in Ia IIae, q. 94, a. 4, this example is also mentioned in the following: IIa IIae, q. 51, a. 4; ibid, q. 62, a. 5, ad 1; ibid, q. 120, a. 1; In V Ethic., lect. 12; 1 In III Sent, d. 37, q. 1, a. 3; In IV Sent., d. 33, q. 1, a. 2, ad 1.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Ia IIae, q. 94, a. 4.

    Google Scholar 

  58. For a discussion on the role of the practical syllogism in moral reasoning, see, D. J. Allan, “The Practical Syllogism”, Autour d’Aristote, Recueil d’études offert à Monseigneur A. Mansion, Louvain, 1955, pp. 325-340.

    Google Scholar 

  59. The Nicomachean Ethics, I, 3, 1094b 24-27; cf. M. B. Crowe, op. cit., pp. 209-210.

    Google Scholar 

  60. Ia IIae, q. 94, a. 4.

    Google Scholar 

  61. Ia IIae, q. 94, a. 4.

    Google Scholar 

  62. Ia IIae, q. 94, a. 4.

    Google Scholar 

  63. O. Lottin, “La Valeur des formules de S. Thomas d’Aquin concernant la loi naturelle,” art. Mélanges Joseph Maréchal, II, p. 371.

    Google Scholar 

  64. O. Lottin, “La Valeur des formules de S. Thomas d’Aquin concernant la loi naturelle,” p. 371. cf. W. Conway, “Situation Ethics”, I.T.Q., 21 (1954), p. 61; he agrees with Lottin in arguing that certain secondary precepts, because of the way they are formulated, make provision for particular circumstances, so that the practical conclusions from the application of these principles to concrete situations may vary with the circumstances.

    Google Scholar 

  65. J. Rickaby, Oxford and Cambridge Conferences, 2nd series, London, 1902, pp. 18–19.

    Google Scholar 

  66. J. Fuchs, Theologia Moralis Generalis, pp. 81-82: “Exempli causa, propositio ‘depositum reddendum est’ nondum respicit limitationem possibilem iuris; principium ‘non licet alios occidere’ non addit conditiones ‘directe’ et ‘propria auctoritate privata’, negligens sic quaes-tiones poenae capitis, defensionis sui, auctorizationis divinae in materia iuris (cfr. casum Abraham-Isaac); norma ‘non licet auferre invito domino rem alienam’ non indicat possi-bilitatem transferendi ius in aliud subiectum iuris, sive ex parte Dei sive per legitimam auc-toritatem” cited by M. B. Crowe, “Human Nature—Immutable or Mutable?”, p. 217.

    Google Scholar 

  67. A. D. Sertillanges, La philosophie morale de S. Thomas d’Aquin, p. 112: “Là donc où les principes seconds, appliqués selon leur teneur propre, risqueraient de compromettre, au lieu de la servir, l’efficacité des principes premiers, que ce soit sur le même terrain, que ce soit sur un autre, il devient nécessaire de suspendre l’application, et, si l’on peut transposer ainsi cette formule fameuse, “sortir de la légalité pour rentrer dans le droit,” c’est-à-dire, ici, abandonner la formule générale de l’application pour la valeur universelle du principe, c’est la sagesse.”

    Google Scholar 

  68. R. Jolivet, Traité de philosophie, Morale, p. 117; cf. H. Rommen, The Natural Law, pp. 224-225. This writer, as with Jolivet, is prepared, without offering any explanation, to speak of “principles which do not apply with universality.”

    Google Scholar 

  69. A. Van Hove, Prolegomena ad Codicem Juris Canonici, Malines, 1945, n. 55.

    Google Scholar 

  70. A. Van Hove, op. cit., n. 52: “In his ergo quae iure naturae praecipiuntur, praecepta primaria et secundaria non sunt distinguenda, cum omnia aeque sint imposita iure naturae.”

    Google Scholar 

  71. See above pp. 162-163.

    Google Scholar 

  72. For a detailed statement of Jolivet’s position, see above pp. 16-18.

    Google Scholar 

  73. IIa IIae, q. 33, a. 2; cf. In 3 Sent., d. 25, q. 2, a. 1, ad 3.

    Google Scholar 

  74. Ia IIae, q. 71, a. 5, ad 3; cf. Ia Pars, q. 88, a. 1, ad 2; IIa IIae, q. 3, a. 2, q. 79, a. 3, ad 3, q. 140, a. 2, ad 2; In 3 Sent., d. 25, q. 2, a. 1, ad 2; In 4 Sent., d. 15, q. 2, a. 1.

    Google Scholar 

  75. The classical distinction between counsels and precepts is usually formulated as follows: a “counsel” is a maximum standard or ideal at which men ought to aim, a “precept” is a minimum standrad below which men must not fall. It will be remembered that Lottin and Van Overbeke put forward the suggestion that some of the secondary precepts authorised by S. Thomas in the Commentary on the Sentences are not really part of the natural law because the natural law does not oblige us to fulfil them. As we noted in the teaching of Van Overbeke, such precepts are required not by the demand but by the recommendations of nature. While disagreeing with the view expressed by these two writers over the question of interpretation in the Commentary on the Sentences, we would agree that “counsels” do not constitute part of the content of natural law.

    Google Scholar 

  76. O. Lottin, “La Valeur des formules de S. Thomas d’Aquin concernant la loi naturelle,” pp. 371–372.

    Google Scholar 

  77. Suppl, q. 41, a. 1, ad 3; De Malo, q. 2, a. 4, ad 13; IIa IIae, q. 57, a. 2, ad 1.

    Google Scholar 

  78. R. J. Deferrari and M. I. Barry, Complete Index of the Summa Theologica, Washington, 1956, p. 119. Although not all dealing with human nature and the question of natural law, there are well over 3,000 references to be found for the term natura. This makes clear the apparent unimportance of the notion of “mutable” human nature.

    Google Scholar 

  79. This section of the Summa Theologica was compiled after S. Thomas’s death by drawing on appropriate passages from the Commentary on the Sentences, and shaping them to the plan S. Thomas had already outlined. Therefore, although the Supplementum is part of the Summa Theologica, it in fact represents S. Thomas’s thought of the period twenty years before.

    Google Scholar 

  80. Nichomachean Ethics, VII, lect. 14.

    Google Scholar 

  81. Suppl, q. 41, a. 1, ad 3.

    Google Scholar 

  82. De Malo, q. 2, a. 4, ad 13.

    Google Scholar 

  83. M. B. Crowe, “Human Nature—Immutable or Mutable?” p. 225.

    Google Scholar 

  84. IIa IIae, q. 57, a. 2.

    Google Scholar 

  85. See above, pp. 164-170.

    Google Scholar 

  86. cf. M. B. Crowe, “Human Nature—Mutable or Immutable?”, p. 226; speaking of this mutability describes it as, “that which makes possible a change in the will of depositor usually well-intentioned about the use he will put his property to, but possibly ill-intentioned.”

    Google Scholar 

  87. J. Fuchs, Theologia Moralis Generalis, Pars Prima, Rome, 1960, pp. 77–81; cf. R. Jolivet, Traité de Philosophie: Morale, Lyons-Paris, 1962, pp. 119-123.

    Google Scholar 

  88. J. Fuchs, loc. cit., p. 77.

    Google Scholar 

  89. M. B. Crowe, “Human Nature—Immutable or Mutable?”, p. 215.

    Google Scholar 

  90. J. Fuchs, loc. cit., pp. 79-81.

    Google Scholar 

  91. L. Oeing-Hanhoff, “Thomas von Aquin und die Situation des Thomismus Heute,” Philosophisches Jahrbuch, 70 (1962), pp. 17–33. cf. For an article dealing with the mutability of human nature from the point of view of social anthropology, see, C. Fay, “Human Evolution: a Challenge to Thomistic Ethics,” International Philosophical Quarterly, 2 (1960), pp. 50-80.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1966 Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, Netherlands

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Armstrong, R.A. (1966). The Concept of Variability among the Secondary Precepts of Natural Law. In: Primary and Secondary Precepts in Thomistic Natural Law Teaching. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-9388-7_6

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-9388-7_6

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-011-8613-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-011-9388-7

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics