Skip to main content

Some Comments on the Validity and Usefulness of the Distinction Between Primary and Secondary Precepts

  • Chapter
Primary and Secondary Precepts in Thomistic Natural Law Teaching

Abstract

We stated at the end of the status quaestionis that this chapter would be concerned with drawing some conclusions from the teaching of S. Thomas, and applying them to certain basic questions of natural law in the hope that some confused issues might be clarified. There are three points we propose to bring forward for discussion in this chapter.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. O. Lottin, Morale Fondamentale, Tournai, 1954, pp. 183–184.

    Google Scholar 

  2. We noted the following writers in particular. H. Capitant, Introduction à l’étude du droit civil, Paris, 1923, p. 35 and 187; V. Cathrein, Recht, Naturrecht und Positives Recht, Freiburg 1909, pp. 132-133; Ed. Janssens, Cours de morale générale, t. I, Louvain, 1926, pp. 219-222; F. Gény, Science et technique en droit privé positif, Paris, 1913–1924, t. II, p. 173; C. Martyniak, Le fondement objectif du droit d’après saint Thomas d’Aquin, Paris, 1931, p. 97; L. Le Fur, Les grands problèmes du droit, Paris, 1937, p. 181

    Google Scholar 

  3. This terminology is suggested by O. Lottin, Morale Fondamentale, pp. 177-178

    Google Scholar 

  4. O. Lottin, loc. cit., p. 177. This writer also refers to S. Paul’s famous text from the Epistle to the Romans, chapter 2, verses 14-15.

    Google Scholar 

  5. For details concerning the dates this work is believed to have been written, see above, pp. 58-59.

    Google Scholar 

  6. See above, pp. 74-75.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Suppl, q. 65, a. 2, (italics mine).

    Google Scholar 

  8. In 2 Sent., d. 24, q. 2, a. 3; see also, In 2 Sent, d. 39, q. 3, a. 1.

    Google Scholar 

  9. For details concerning the date this work was written, see above, p. 83-84.

    Google Scholar 

  10. In V Ethic, lect. 12.

    Google Scholar 

  11. See above, pp. 84-85.

    Google Scholar 

  12. For details concerning the dates the several parts of this work were written, see above, pp. 86-87.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Ia IIae, q. 94, a. 4.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Ia IIae, q. 94, a. 4, ad 2.

    Google Scholar 

  15. See above, Chpt. II, also pp. 37-38.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Ia IIae, q. 94, a. 4.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Ia IIae, q. 94, a. 4.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Ia IIae, q. 94, a. 4, ad 2.

    Google Scholar 

  19. cf. J. Dabin, The Legal Philosophies of Lask, Radbruch and Dahin, Cambridge, Mass., 1950, pp. 420–421. He refers to the lack of precision regarding the placing of the boundary lines between the different classes of precepts; see also, P. M. Van Overbeke, “La loi naturelle et le droit naturel selon S. Thomas,” Revue Thomiste, 57 (1957), p. 470, who refers to “the inevitable imprecision of the limits involved in the class of secondary precepts.”

    Google Scholar 

  20. See above, pp. 3-7.

    Google Scholar 

  21. See above, pp. 7-14.

    Google Scholar 

  22. See above, pp. 14-21.

    Google Scholar 

  23. V. Cathrein, Recht, Naturrecht und Positives Recht, Freiburg, 1909, pp. 132–133, cf. note the statement of this same principle on p. 222.

    Google Scholar 

  24. V. Cathrein, loc. cit., p. 133.

    Google Scholar 

  25. See above, pp. 93-97.

    Google Scholar 

  26. See above, pp. 3-4.

    Google Scholar 

  27. For an outline of the “restricted” view of natural law as found in the writers during the century before S. Thomas see, O. Lottin, Le droit naturel chez saint Thomas et ses prédécesseurs, Bruges, 1931; also, Ph. Delhaye, “Le droit naturel: recherches historiques et doctrinales,” L’Ami du Clergé, 69 (1959), pp. 617-625, 681-685; 70 (1960) pp. 33-39, 97-103, 145-153, 225-228.

    Google Scholar 

  28. H. Capitant, Introduction à l’étude du droit civil, Paris, 1923, p. 35; see above, pp. 4-5.

    Google Scholar 

  29. L. Le Fur, Les grands problèmes du droit, Paris, 1937, p. 181.

    Google Scholar 

  30. See above, pp. 7-8.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Ed. Janssens, Cours de morale générale, t. I, Louvain, 1926, p. 222. 6 Ed. Janssens, loc. cit., p. 218.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Ed. Janssens, loc. cit., p. 219.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Ia IIae, q. 94, a. 2 and a. 4; this same point is discussed in Ia IIae, q. 100, a. 1; see above, p. 25.

    Google Scholar 

  34. See above, pp. 35-36.

    Google Scholar 

  35. See above, pp. 36-37.

    Google Scholar 

  36. See above, pp. 40-41.

    Google Scholar 

  37. See above, p. 47.

    Google Scholar 

  38. See above, p. 48.

    Google Scholar 

  39. See above, p. 49.

    Google Scholar 

  40. See above, p. 50.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Ia IIae, q. 100, a. 3; see above, p. 109.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Ia IIae, q. 100, a. 3; see above, p. 109.

    Google Scholar 

  43. See above, pp. 104-105.

    Google Scholar 

  44. I. Trethowan, “The Philosophical Concept of Morality,” in, The Springs of Morality, London, 1956, p. 9.

    Google Scholar 

  45. See above, p. 40.

    Google Scholar 

  46. E. D’Arcy, Conscience and its Right to Freedom, p. 54. cf. p. 54, where this writer criticises A. Vermeersch for not distinguishing between the principle “good should be done and evil shunned” and the following two: “laws should be obeyed,” “promises should be kept.” Of the principle “good should be done,” D’Arcy comments, “the important thing is that we constantly use it, not that we readily enunciate it; it does not matter very much if we never explicitly formulate it at all.” cf., A. Vermeersch, Theologiae Moralis Principia, I, Rome, 1923, p. 289.

    Google Scholar 

  47. See above, p. 41.

    Google Scholar 

  48. E. D’Arcy, op. cit., p. 60.

    Google Scholar 

  49. cf. Suppl., q. 65, a. 1.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Suppl., q. 65, a. 1; see above, pp. 68-71.

    Google Scholar 

  51. See above, pp. 74-75.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Suppl., q. 65, a. 2.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Ia IIae q. 100, a. 6; cf. Suppl., q. 65, a. 1, ad 9, where S. Thomas states the following: “natural inclinations in the appetitive faculty follow the natural concept in the cognitive faculty.”

    Google Scholar 

  54. See above, pp. 70-71.

    Google Scholar 

  55. For a more extensive statement of this criticism, see above, pp. 70-71.

    Google Scholar 

  56. For a complete statement of this criticism, see above, pp. 72-75.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Suppl., q. 65, a. 2.

    Google Scholar 

  58. Suppl., q. 65, a. 2.

    Google Scholar 

  59. For a statement concerning the primary and secondary ends of marriage, see above, pp. 62-63.

    Google Scholar 

  60. P. M. Van Overbeke, “La loi naturelle et le droit naturel selon S. Thomas,” Revue Thomiste, 57 (1957), p. 470; “les préceptes seconds n’y sont pas de véritables préceptes de vrais commandements, de vraies exigences de la nature humaine, mais plutôt de simples vota naturae”; for this same point by another writer, see, O. Lottin, Morale Fondamentale, p. 180.

    Google Scholar 

  61. cf. J. Cunnane, The Natural Moral Law, (unpublished thesis), Maynooth, 1941, p. 176; “This distinction between primary and secondary precepts, has no other justification except to meet the Biblical cases of the real or apparent breaches of the natural law. The dragging in of a Divine inspiration into this, rather than any other application of the natural law, is not convincing.”

    Google Scholar 

  62. Ia IIae, q. 94, a. 5; we note this same thought already expressed in the Commentary on the Ethics. In V Ethic, lect. 12.

    Google Scholar 

  63. See above, pp. 92-93.

    Google Scholar 

  64. See above, pp. 93-97.

    Google Scholar 

  65. For a discussion and an example of the form of procedure to be followed, see pp. 129-130.

    Google Scholar 

  66. See above, pp. 100-102.

    Google Scholar 

  67. In V Ethic, Iect. 12: “Necesse est quod quidquid ex justo naturali sequitur, quasi con-clusio, sit justum naturale”; cf. P. M. Van Overbeke, op. cit., p. 470. He states that the degree of deduction matters very little whether it is “close” or “distant”. In the light of this teaching he suggests we dispense with the term propinquus.

    Google Scholar 

  68. O. Lottin, Le droit naturel chez saint Thomas et ses prédécesseurs, Bruges, 1931, p. 98.

    Google Scholar 

  69. P. M. Van Overbeke, op. cit., p. 470. cf. J. Dabin, The General Theory of Law, in The Legal Philosophies of Lask, Radbruch and Dabin, Cambridge, Mass., p. 421.

    Google Scholar 

  70. See above, pp. 100-102.

    Google Scholar 

  71. O. Lottin, Morale Fondamentale, p. 183.

    Google Scholar 

  72. O. Lottin, Morale Fondamentale, p. 183.

    Google Scholar 

  73. O. Lottin, op. cit., p. 183, “est-il nécessaire, ou même utile, de conserver cette formule dans l’enseignement didactique des écoles”?

    Google Scholar 

  74. P. M. Van Overbeke, op. cit., pp. 469-470; “cette distinction selon la doctrine du Commentaire sur les Sentences pourrait être franchement abandonnée, comme d’ailleurs saint Thomas lui-même semble l’avoir fait, puisqu’il n’en parle déjà plus dans le Summa contra Gentiles. Le vrai motif de cet abandon nous semble des plus obvies: les préceptes “seconds” n’y sont pas de véritables préceptes, de vrais commandements, de vraies exigences de la nature humaine, mais plutôt de simples vota naturae.”

    Google Scholar 

  75. R. F. Bégin, Natural Law and Positive Law, Washington, 1959, p. 85.

    Google Scholar 

  76. S. Bertke, The Possibility of Invincible Ignorance of the Natural Law, Washington, 1941, p. 63.

    Google Scholar 

  77. Ia IIae, q. 94, a. 4.

    Google Scholar 

  78. Ia IIae, q. 77, a. 2, q. 58, a. 5, q. 94, a. 4: Suppl., q. 54, a. 3, ad 2.

    Google Scholar 

  79. Ia IIae., q. 10, a. 1; cf., Ia IIae., q. 94, a. 6.

    Google Scholar 

  80. S. Bertke, op. cit., p. 73.

    Google Scholar 

  81. S. Bertke, op. cit., p. 73.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1966 Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, Netherlands

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Armstrong, R.A. (1966). Some Comments on the Validity and Usefulness of the Distinction Between Primary and Secondary Precepts. In: Primary and Secondary Precepts in Thomistic Natural Law Teaching. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-9388-7_5

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-9388-7_5

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-011-8613-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-011-9388-7

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics