Skip to main content

Monistic Theories of Absolute Obligation: Utilitarianism

  • Chapter
Meta-Ethics and Normative Ethics
  • 159 Accesses

Abstract

There have been persistent attempts during the history of ethics to explain all valuation and all obligation in terms of one basic source. Many such theories are basically meta-ethical theories which suggest that all concepts can be explained in terms of and reduced to one concept, and that to a natural phenomenon. It has been argued in Part A that such meta-theories are mistaken. However, monistic theories can be advanced purely as normative theories. It is impossible here to consider all the actual and logically possible monistic normative theories, and I shall, accordingly, confine my attention to the most important of them, namely, the utilitarian theories. Here I shall be concerned to argue that whilst utilitarianism can be and has been stated as a simple, straightforward monistic theory, in fact it has come to be modified and restated in ways which make it a pluralistic theory, and this in order to avoid difficulties encountered by the simple monistic version.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. “Extreme and Restricted Utilitarianism”, Philosophical Quarterly, 6, 1956, p. 346.

    Google Scholar 

  2. “Interpretations of Mill’s ‘Utilitarianism’”, Philosophical Quarterly, 6, 1956, pp. 118–9.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Principia Ethica: Cambridge, C.U.P., 1903: pp. 162-4. (Reprinted with the permission of Cambridge University Press).

    Google Scholar 

  4. “An Examination of Restricted Utilitarianism”, The Philosophical Review, LXVI, 1957, pp. 466–485.

    Google Scholar 

  5. See my “A Non-Utilitarian Approach to Punishment”, Inquiry, 8, 1965, pp. 249–263. A very carefully and thoughtfully argued utilitarian reply to such examples has been set out by T. L. S. Sprigge in “A Utilitarian Reply to Dr. McCloskey”, (Inquiry, 8, 1965, pp. 264-291). My reply to Sprigge’s arguments is set out in “Utilitarian and Retributive Punishment”, Journal of Philosophy, LXIV, 1967, pp. 91-110. Sprigge argues that it is less often the case that the utilitarian is committed to unjust punishment than my discussion and my examples suggest, but he acknowledges that utilitarianism may dictate the infliction of unjust punishment. He suggests that when this is so, the punishment is morally justified, even though we may regret its necessity. In reply I have argued that if we consider possible and actual examples of useful, unjust punishment, e.g. of a person wrongly believed to be a responsible, free moral agent, it is evident that it is not the case that such punishment is usually morally justified. On the contrary, much such punishment is morally abhorrent to us, and where it is practised, we regard it as a social and political evil which should be eradicated. It is at least in part because we are concerned with justice in punishment, that so many of us are concerned to inculcate into the community at large an understanding of what constitutes free conduct for which the person can properly be held to be answerable. The widespread campaign to have alcoholism treated as a form of sickness and not as a crime, is part of this endeavour. It is hoped that by so educating the general public, the demand for punishment which is unjust (although often useful) will weaken or even cease.

    Google Scholar 

  6. “The Complexity of the Concepts of Punishment”, Philosophy, XXXVII, 1962, pp. 307–325.

    Google Scholar 

  7. See my note: “ ‘Suppose Everyone Did The Same?’ — A Note”, Mind, LXXV, 1966, pp. 432–3.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Principles of Morals and Legislation, ch. 1.

    Google Scholar 

  9. “Extreme and Restricted Utilitarianism”, Philosophical Quarterly, 6, 1965, p. 353. See also Smart’s An Outline of a System of Utilitarian Ethics, Melbourne, Melbourne University Press, 1961.

    Google Scholar 

  10. The Methods of Ethics, Bk. IV, ch. iv, 7th Edition, p. 467.

    Google Scholar 

  11. The rich variety of utilitarian, and in particular, of rule utilitarian theories which could be devised by ingenious and imaginative utilitarians is suggested by Brandt in his “Towards a Credible Form of Utilitarianism” (Chapter 4 of Morality and the Language of Conduct, edited Hector-Neri Castaneda and George Nakhnikian, Detroit, Wayne State University Press, 1963). Brandt’s final version runs: “An act is right if and only if it conforms with that learnable set of rules the recognition of which as morally binding — roughly at the time of the act — by everyone in the society of the agent, except for the retention by individuals of already formed and decided moral convictions, would maximize intrinsic value.” (p. 139) Such a theory would have to be placed as a synthesis of the moral principles and rule-in-practice versions of rule utilitarianism distinguished above.

    Google Scholar 

  12. pp. 130-6.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Ethics, pp. 230 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  14. The Place of Reason in Ethics, Cambridge, C.U.P. Press, 1950, pp. 150-1.

    Google Scholar 

  15. See J. J. C. Smart: “Extreme and Restricted Utilitarianism”: Philosophical Quarterly 6, 1956, pp. 344–354.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. “Interpretations of Mill’s ‘Utilitarianism’”, Philosophical Quarterly, 6, 1956, p. 119.

    Google Scholar 

  17. See J. Rawls, “Two Concepts of Rules”, Philosophical Review, LXIV, 1955, pp. 3–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. See “The Complexity of the Concepts of Punishment”, Philosophy, XXXVII, 1962, pp. 307–325, “A Non-Utilitarian Approach to Punishment”, Inquiry, 8, 1965, and “Utilitarian and Retributive Punishment”, Journal of Philosophy, LXVI, 1967, pp. 91-110.

    Google Scholar 

  19. For a discussion of further difficulties of this theory see my article “An Examination of Restricted Utilitarianism”, Philosophical Review, LXVI, 1957, pp. 466–485.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1969 Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, Netherlands

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

McCloskey, H.J. (1969). Monistic Theories of Absolute Obligation: Utilitarianism. In: Meta-Ethics and Normative Ethics. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-9299-6_7

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-9299-6_7

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-011-8544-8

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-011-9299-6

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics