Skip to main content

The Aesthetic Symbol

  • Chapter
Art and Analysis
  • 78 Accesses

Abstract

Popular usage has it that art is a language. For example music is a language, the language of love, or the universal language. In reply to this bit of folk wisdom some philosophers have pointed out that a language is made up of symbols. A symbol is something carrying a meaning, and as such it exists to be understood, to impart information whether conceptual or factual. If a work of art is a symbol, then its value is either cognitive or practical and its purpose is to carry information. Almost with one accord, though, aestheticians deny that art is either cognitive or practical in its proper function. Consequently most of them reject the theory that a work of art is a symbol as a visciously intellectualistic theory which misses the whole meaning of fine art.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. “L’art est l’expression de l’invisible par des signes naturels qui le manifestent.” T. Jouffroy, Cours d’A esthétique … “To be called beautiful a thing must be significant in virtue of its sensible character or of the sensuous images it arouses in our minds, which is to say that the symbolism must be natural or’ second nature’, not conventional or accidental.” E. F. Carritt, An Introduction to Aesthetics, London, p. 23.

    Google Scholar 

  2. The footprint might also be responded to as a signal or a symptom, in which case it is taken as a stimulus to action with no consciousness of the conformation in pattern between the symbol and the symbolized. A bloodhound would respond to the footprint as a signal.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Language and Myth, trans. S. K. Langer, N.Y., 1945, see especially chapter 6. Also cf. C. H. Hamburg, Symbol and Reality, Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague/Netherlands, 1956, Chapter II.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Poetics, xxi, trans. Bywater.

    Google Scholar 

  5. E.g. N. Cazden, “Toward a Theory of Realism in Music,” Jl. Aesth. and Art Criticism, X, (1951), 135–151.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  6. Essay on Man, Yale, (1944), p. 168; also of his Philosophy of Symbolic Forms, New Haven, 1953, vol I, p. 177 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Ibid., p. 146.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Philosophy in a New Key, Harvard University Press, 1942, chap. 9 More recently she has said that dynamic pattern “copies the form of vital feeling,” Feeling and Form, N.Y. 1953, p. 67.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Journal of Philosophy, XL, no. 12, 1943, pp. 325-326.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Feeling and Form, p. 31.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Ibid., p. 380.

    Google Scholar 

  12. “Aesthetic and the Theory of Signs”, Jl. of Unified Science, VIII 1939, 131-150; Signs, Language and Behavior, New York, (1946), chs. v, vii. “Science, Art, and Technology,” Kenyon Review I, Spring, 1939; Cf. Mrs. Louise N. Roberts, “Art as Icon; An Interpretation of C. W. Morris” Tulane Studies in Philosophy, vol. IV, pp. 75-83. Cf. also Max Rieser “The Semantic Theory of Art in America”,J. of Aesthetics and Art Crit. XV, (1956), pp. 12-26.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Ibid., p. 193.

    Google Scholar 

  14. “On Semiotic Aesthetics,”J. of Aesthetics and Art Crit., X, (1951), 67-77.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Morris also defines the iconic sign as “any sign which is similar in some respects to what it denotes.” and adds, “iconicity is thus a matter of degree,” Signs, Language and Behavior, N.Y., (1946), p. 191.

    Google Scholar 

  16. “One of the dangers of the use of models in science, for instance, arises out of the temptation to ascribe to the subject matter of a theory properties of the model illustrating the theory which are not involved in the theory itself,” Ibid, p. 23.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Another difficult problem, growing out of the preceding, is the problem of determining the degree of similarity (iconicity) between symbol and referent in the aesthetic situation. I shall suggest later that this problem belongs to the psychology of the aesthetic experience.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Kant’s Critique of Aesthetic Judgment, ed. J. C. Meredith, Oxford (1911) 175-176.

    Google Scholar 

  19. “Poetry, Myth and Reality,” The Language of Poetry, ed. A. Tate, Princeton, 1942.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Cf. Appendix.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1957 Springer Science + Business Media B.V.

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Ballard, E.G. (1957). The Aesthetic Symbol. In: Art and Analysis. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-8843-2_4

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-8843-2_4

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-011-8193-8

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-011-8843-2

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics