Skip to main content

Abstract

Plato was the first to apply the term ‘element’ to the basic constituents of all things. So Diels tells us in his interesting history, Elementum1. Element (στοιχεĩον) had been a common word in Greek to denote letters of the alphabet, corresponding to our ‘ABC’s’. But it was put to philosophic use first in the Theaete- tus (201e). Socrates says that he remembers in a dream having heard someone say that things were built up out of prior things, just as the alphabet arises from letters2. (See 203a f., Rep. 402a f.) One need not accept Diels at all points. For example, his statement is rather extreme that the theory of elements never belonged to the heart of Plato’s philosophy, but was a late, Pythagorean development. Nor need one accept his puzzling interpretation that the term ‘element’, applied first to geometrical figure, was used later by Plato to describe the one and infinite two. And the eventual demonological meaning of the term lies beyond the scope of the present study 3.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. H. Diels, Elementum (Leipzig, 1899).

    Google Scholar 

  2. Ibid., p. 58. Diels thinks that Plato got the usage from the Atomists; Taylor differs Taylor, A Commentary on Plato’s Timaeus (Oxford, 1928), p. 307.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Diels, op. cit., pp. 21-2, 57-8.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Ibid., pp. 58, 81-2.

    Google Scholar 

  5. As beginning: Prot. 318a, Phaedr. 237b, d, 262d, Parm. 137d, 153c, Rep. 2.377a, Laws 6.753e, 768d, 775e, 2.671a, 672c, Gorg. 466b, Tim. 48b. As leader, ruler: Prot. 344c. As non-material principle: Phaedr. 245cd, Phaedo lole, Rep. 6.510b, 511bc.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Taylor, op. cit., p. 393, cf. De Gen. et Corr. 325b28-9 and Tim. 53d.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Cf. his use of ἀρχή in the references listed in Bonitz, Index Aristotelicus (Berlin, 1870), 111a28-113b26.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Under no circumstances should the fire, earth, air, and water we know be confused with the kinds mentioned by Plato, for he identifies them by nature rather than by our experience of them. Cf. Cornford, Plato’s Cosmology (London, 1937), pp. 188-91 and Tim. 50b.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Cf. De Gen. et Corr. 330b34-33la3. Aristotle has the same intermediates.

    Google Scholar 

  10. With’ square’ numbers, only one mean is required in the proportion, but in’ solid’ or cubic numbers, two mean terms are required, as: x3: x2y::x2y: xy2:: xy2: y3. Cf. Heath, A History of Greek Mathematics (Oxford, 1921), I, 89, 297.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Zeller, Plato (London, 1888), pp. 372-3n Philolaos connected the fifth element with ether as did Xenocrates, who (apud Simpl. Phys. 205b Schol. in Aris. 427a) attributes this view to Plato. Zeller disagrees, but cites Martin, 111, 140 sq., as concurring. Burnet’s demonstration that the fragments of Philolaos are probably apocryphal makes dependence on them a risky business. (Plato, Timée-Critias (Paris, 1949), Vol. X of Budé ed., tr., ed., and intro. by A. Rivaud, pp. 24, 24n, 81-82, citing Burnet, Early Greek Philosophy, ed. 3, pp. 277, 284-303.) As is well known, Aristotle’s fifth element was ether (see Zeller, Aristotle (London, I897), pp. 476-7). Although one can speculate that the alacrity with which Plato’s followers accepted ‘ether’ as the fifth element might show that it arose in the Academy and was put forth before Plato’s death (Jaeger, Aristotle (Oxford, 1948), pp. 300-1 and 300n.), there is no real proof that this was Plato’s view. Rivaud (Timée-Critias, Budé, p. 84) thinks in contrast to the above that Plato’s followers considered ether a variety of fire.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Rivaud, Timée-Critias (Budé ed.), pp. 117, 81-2.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Sachs, Die fuenf platonischen Koerper (Berlin, 1917), pp. 186, 105. Cf. Burnet, op. cit. (ed. 4), pp. 283-4, 293, rejecting the hypothesis that the Pythagoreans introduced them.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Cf. Phaedo nob, where it is said that the true earth, if seen from above, is many-colored, like the balls made of twelve pieces of leather. Robin, Greek Thought (London, 1928), p. 227, suggests that the number of pentagonal surfaces in this element remind one of the twelve signs of the zodiac, which are like an adornment for the sky. It may, therefore, be the body in which the stars move, namely, the ether. (Cf. Rep. 7.529bc, Epi. 981c.) Rivaud, op. cit., p. 84, is inclined to take this position.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Euclid gives details regarding the construction of the five basic solids in his Elements, XIII, 13-18 and addendum. Cf. Heath, op. cit., I, 415-9.

    Google Scholar 

  16. As may be confirmed by reasons already given as well as by the apology with which he prefaces the passage cited. His method, Plato says, is ‘technical’ and ‘most unusual’ (53bc).

    Google Scholar 

  17. Some think this the starting point of Plato’s later theory of the derivation of the world from square and cubic numbers. E.g., Stenzel, Zahl und Gestalt bei Platon und Aristoteles (Leipzig, 1933), pp. 88-9, 70-1.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Aristotle even follows Plato in the use of ἐπίπεδος in this passage.

    Google Scholar 

  19. πέρας or ὅρος. The word ὅρος, which occurs frequently in the Prior Analytics, is found more rarely in the Posterior Analytics. This was taken by Solmsen to be the last link in Aristotle’s gradual development from a Platonic view of form to something purely logical in implication. (Ross, Aristotle’s Prior and Posterior Analytics (Oxford, 1949), p. 16). This conforms to the chronological view adopted in this study.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Shorey, in American Journal of Philology, IX, 4; 416.

    Google Scholar 

  21. See arrangement in Oxford tr., Physics, 212b32 n., as listed by R. P. Hardie.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Rep. 7, esp. 524b-531c. Cf. Heath, op. cit., I, 284-7, Burnet, Greek Philosophy, Part I (London, 1924), pp. 224-8.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Mansion, Introduction a la Physique Aristotélicienne (Louvain, 1946), p. 225, citing 299a11-7.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Ross, op. cit., p. 14. The doctrine applies to his whole work, not just to an early ‘Platonic period’. Cf. the chronology in Chapter One, supra, and Mansion, op. cit., pp. 192-3.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Called ‘metaphysics’ by later gneraetions.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Plato in 56ab makes the pyramids cut, but he does not mean by virtue of their geometrical nature only (Cornford, op. cit., p. 222).

    Google Scholar 

  27. E.g., ‘sandpaper scratches because it is rough’.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Joachim in his edition of Aristotle On Coming-to-be and Passing-away (Oxford, 1922), p. 76, referring to his notes in Oxford tr. to 968a9-12. Aristotle is probably not the genuine author of De Lineis Insecabilibus. Ross, Aristotle (London, 1945), P 13, finds it primarily directed against Xenocrates, and to resemble in its doctrine Theophrastus, to whom Simplicius ascribed it; Strato has also been suggested as its author. W.S. Hett in Aristotle Minor Works (Loeb ed.), p. 415, says only that this ‘most interesting” and ‘extremely difficult’ work was written by some author of the Peripatetic School. At any rate, it is in conformity with Aristotle’s position in his recognized works.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Burnet, Early Greek Philosophy (ed. 4; London, 1948), pp. 290-1. He notes that Zeller differs. Cf. Meta. M, 6, 1080b18 f. and De Caelo, 3ooa16.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Milhaud, Les Philosophes-Géomètres de la Grèce (Paris, 1900), p. 341. Cf. Meta., Delta.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Cherniss, op. cit., I, pp. 131-2. See Meta. 1091b30-5, 1028021-4, and 1085b27-34. Cf. Ross, Aristotle’s Metaphysics (Oxford, 1924), II, p. 457 n. 32.

    Google Scholar 

  32. 1016b1-6, 23;1034a8 fin.; 104434-9; 1045b23;1052329-36; 1088b14-16, 25-8. Also, De Anima, 412b6-9, 430b14-20, 27-31. This does not affect, of course, his general attack on the divisibility of solids, to be found in De Gen. et Corr., 325b25-326b7.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Vs. Cherniss, op. cit., I, 150.

    Google Scholar 

  34. As Martin did, cf. Cornford, op. cit., p. 229.

    Google Scholar 

  35. There is a striking parallel between the rigid field convention of modern quantum physics and the Receptacle of Plato. Both are delimited in order for solid bodies to appear. Solid bodies of any type can appear anywhere, subject only to the delimiting factors involved (object-particles in the case of modern physics, planes in the case of Plato) and other bodies in the field. Both are ‘nothing ‘until delimited, but potentially everything. This was first brought to the writer’s attention by Dr. Nels Lindenblad of Princeton, N.J. Cf. Eddington, Fundamental Theory (Cambridge, 1946), pp. 22-5.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1954 Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, Netherlands

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Claghorn, G.S. (1954). Aristotle’s Criticism of the Simple Bodies. In: Aristotle’s Criticism of Plato’s ‘Timaeus’. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-8839-5_3

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-8839-5_3

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-011-8190-7

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-011-8839-5

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics