Skip to main content
  • 81 Accesses

Abstract

In the foreword to Von Hegel, Löwith states that he has no intention of writing a “Geistesgeschichte in the usual sense of the word” since its principles “evolving from Hegel’s metaphysics of the spirit have become so attenuated that they are now trivial.” Rather he seeks “to bring accurately to life the epoch which starts with Hegel and ends with Nietzsche, ‘transcribing’ the philosophical history of the nineteenth century within the horizon of the present.” But in sharp contrast to the “transcribing” activities of many of his contemporaries, Löwith emphasizes that “to transcribe history does not mean to counterfeit the irrevocable power of what has taken place once and for all, or to increase vitality at the expense of truth, but to do justice to the vital fact of history that the tree may be known only by its fruits, the father by his son.” Thus Löwith’s “transcription” of the intellectual developments of the nineteenth century is based on the view that past and present are intimately related and manifest fundamental similarities. “Hegel seems to stand very far removed from us and Nietzsche very near, if we consider only the latter’s influence and the former’s works. In fact, though, Hegel’s work mediated through his pupils had an effect upon intellectual and political life which it would be difficult to overestimate, while the numerous influences exerted by Nietzsche since 1890 have given birth to a German ideology only in our own time. The Nietzscheans of yesterday correspond to the Hegelians of the 1840’s.” 1

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Löwith, translation of Von Hegel, pp. v–vi.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Löwith, first edition of Von Hegel, p. 530.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Löwith, translation of Von Hegel, p. 64.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Ibid., p. 67. This is certainly a far cry from Löwith’s earlier view of the young-Hegelians as writers “whose real ambitions were not to surpass the experiences of life per se and of human understanding. They return again to the ‘human all too human,’ even to the all too human dimension of knowledge.” Along with the belief in something like “pure thinking” or “absolute consciousness,” they also lack every real potentiality for the extravagance of conceptual thinking. “Feuerbach und der Ausgang,” p. 327.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Löwith, translation of Von Hegel, pp. 80–82.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Quoted in Ibid., p. 102.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Ibid., p. 161.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Ibid., p. 179.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Ibid., pp. 123–124.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Ibid., p. vi. For a remarkably similar view of the development since Hegel see G. Lichtheim, “On the Rim of the Volcano, Heidegger, Bloch, Adorno,” Encounter, XII (1964), pp. 98–105.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Löwith, translation of Von Hegel, pp. 202–205.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Ibid., p. 209.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Quoted in Ibid., p. 84.

    Google Scholar 

  15. “If Hegel causes the eternal to be manifest in the temporal, this is not the result of any formal dialectics, but an intrinsic metaphysics of the Christian logos.” In fact “his philosophy includes within itself the Christian consciousness of the absolute significance of the historical appearance of Christ.” Therefore “not any present moment at all was for him ‘the highest’ but only that which like his own, is a ‘final link’ in the’ sacred chain’ of the past, now appropriated by thought in its full extent.” Hence it is only the time which extends from Thaies to Proclus and from thence to his own age which makes it possible for Hegel to write a period after the ‘now’ of ‘up to now.’ In his unification of all previous history, the accent “is on the entire ‘thus far now,’ that is, ‘finally’ the world spirit has come; and this entirety is a deliberate goal.” Hegel left the question open as to what might proceed from this goal in the future, but because three epochs have now been concluded [one free, some free, all free], “Hegel considered history, taken abstractly, to be ended.” Ibid., pp. 127–129.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Ibid., p. 84 and p. 205.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Ibid., p. 210. In the original German the first sentence of this passage reads “Das wirkliche Kreuz in Hegel’s Analyse der Zeit... etc.” The translator has rendered this as “The true crux in Hegel’s analysis of time” which is literally correct but somewhat vague, hence my interpolation of “crucial point.”

    Google Scholar 

  18. Ibid., pp. 213–214.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Ibid., p. 214.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Ibid., pp. 214–215.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Ibid., p. 216.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Ibid., pp. 216–217. But if Löwith is here highly critical of the consequences of Hegel’s “metaphysical historicism,” his judgment of the young-Hegelians is even more severe. “The actual pupils of Hegel converted his metaphysics of history into an absolute historicism; that is, they retained merely the historical aspect of the absoluteness of the spirit which unfolds historically, and made the events of the age into the supreme power over even philosophy and the spirit.” Thus the young-Hegelians transform Hegel’s retrospective and reminiscent historicism into an historical futurism; they desire to be more than the consequence of history, they want themselves to be epoch-making and thus ‘historic’ Ibid., p. 217.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Ibid., p. 219.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Ibid. In the original German, the last sentence of this paragraph reads, “Und wenn man etwas an der Weltgeschichte bewundern kann dann ist es die Kraft, die Ausdauer und Zähigkeit, mit der sich die Menschheit aus allen Einbussen, Zerstörungen und Verwundungen immer neu wieder herstellt.” The translator has rendered it as follows: “If there is anything in world history to be admired it is the power, the patience, and stubbornness with which it continues to recreate mankind after all losses,, destructions, and injuries [italics mine].”

    Google Scholar 

  25. Ibid., pp. 219–220.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Ibid., pp. 221–222. This tendency to allow the moment to take precedence over other considerations was an underlying motif in all of Goethe’s writings. In his drama Egmont, Goethe has the hero remark, “Do I but live to think about life,” i.e. to speculate historically, “Should I not rather enjoy the present moment?” And in his Faust, Goethe created a character for whom complete bliss can only be attained when he finds the perfect moment, that moment of which he demands, “Please linger; you are so beautiful.” Egmont, III, ii, and Faust, I, iii, in Goethes sämmtliche Werke (Stuttgart and Tübingen: J. G. Cotta’scher Verlag, 1854), I, p. 69 and IX, p. 175.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Löwith, translation of Von Hegel, p. 222.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Quoted in Ibid., p. 223, 225. Löwith also illustrates the primacy of nature in Goethe’s thought by pointing out that “in the midst of the French Revolution, he occupied himself with the metamorphosis of plants, during the campaign in France, with the phenomena of color, and during the July Revolution, with morphology.” Ibid., p. 225.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Ibid., pp. 225–227.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Ibid., p. 227.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Ibid., p. 230.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Ibid., pp. 324 and 200.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Löwith, first edition of Von Hegel, p. 530.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Löwith, translation of Von Hegel, p. 181.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Ibid., p. 82.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Ibid., pp. vi–vii. Löwith also observes in not a single moment of their perpetual change, do time and history per se offer us a place where one can stand firmly. Continuity, duration, and eternity are — independent of the faith in progress, reason, and freedom — [extra-temporal] presuppositions of each and every philosophy of history. First edition of Von Hegel, p. 8.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Ibid., p. 530.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Ibid., p. 9.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1969 Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, Netherlands

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Riesterer, B.P. (1969). Hegel and Goethe. In: Karl Löwith’s View of History: A Critical Appraisal of Historicism. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-7837-2_4

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-7837-2_4

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-011-7839-6

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-011-7837-2

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics