Skip to main content

Phenomenological Communitarianism

  • Chapter
Founding Community

Part of the book series: Phaenomenologica ((PHAE,volume 143))

  • 113 Accesses

Abstract

We saw in the last chapter that certain traditional ethical systems are fundamentally misdirected. The judgmental and relational theories (of which Kantianism and Utilitarianism were, respectively, the obvious examples) exhibit an inherent circularity: the former cannot account for the moral character of the categories it employs and the latter can only evaluate methods and actions while the goals of those actions are inexplicably either moral or amoral. In fact, the problem seems to be that such theories are not invalid, rather they are not theories of the type which can adequately classify acts and judge whether or not they belong to the realm of the moral.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Cf., e.g., Rorty (1991).

    Google Scholar 

  2. Sandel(1984), 17.

    Google Scholar 

  3. MacIntyre (1984), 220.

    Google Scholar 

  4. I do not wish to go into Sandel’s and Maclntyre’s theories in any great detail. Such is not the purpose of this chapter. The specific problems of communitarianism have been documented and discussed in numerous places (Cf. Frazer and Lacey (1993); Buchanan (1989); Rosen-blum (1989); Bell (1993)). Rather, I would like to discuss some of the common traditional problems in communitarian theory as a means of introducing Phenomenological Communitarianism and pointing to its strengths.

    Google Scholar 

  5. The degree to which metaphysical claims are necessary in ethics is highly debated. Cf., e.g., Frazer and Lacey (1993), 149–158, 181–190, and Rawls (1985).

    Google Scholar 

  6. Sandel (1984), 17. Emphasis mine.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Frazer and Lacey (1993), 116. Frazer and Lacey’s point is that feminism is powerless under communitarianism because a woman “cannot find any jumping-off point:…her position as a socially constructed being seems to render her a helpless victim of her situation.”(p.l51) This is an important part of their critique but one with which I cannot deal directly at this time. In the passages which follow, I do hope to show how Phenomenological Communitarianism does not suffer from the problems of the disappearing self, but the specific problem of female subjectivity I have dealt with elsewhere in my “The Possibility of a Feminist Phenomenology,” (1993). 10 See Walzer (1987).

    Google Scholar 

  8. Cf., especially, Hobbes’ Leviathan Ch. XIII and Philosophical Rudiments Ch. I (both in The English Works of Thomas Hobbes, vols. II and III, Sir William Molesworth ed., (London: John Bohn, 1839)). Of course, someone might want to argue that Hobbes’ state of nature is actually an example of a communitarian theory. That is, in this pre-contractual state, individuals are defined by their relationship to each other (even though this relationship is one of war). This would be mistaken, however, because the actors here are clearly individuals, each with an individual good to pursue. These classic Liberal selves are not constituted by their warring relationships and there is no instance of taking up another’s good as such as one’s own. Hobbes’ pre-contractual selves are isolated, individuals who happen to be at war—aggressive monads who want to get together and put an end to chaos for their own good. Perhaps the confusion stems from the use of the term “war.” War seems to carry with it an underlying notion of declarations, sides, and historical struggles. Hobbes’ war has none of these qualities. Each individual fears and is feared by all of the others. Again, this paranoia does not constitute them, though. Their “true nature” is to be something other than paranoid and they long for a sovereign to enforce a contract and create a “society.”

    Google Scholar 

  9. MacIntyre (1972), 466.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Frazer and Lacey (1993), 102.

    Google Scholar 

  11. For this reason, many communitarian theorists refrain from positive claims and simply offer negative critiques of other theories. See, for instance, Frazer and Lacey (1993), 102–03.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Walzer(1987), 20.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Hart (1992), 307.

    Google Scholar 

  14. See Hart (1992), chapter VI, §7–13.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Hart (1992), 458.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Hart (1992), 451.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Walzer (1987), 20,29,30,32.

    Google Scholar 

  18. See Hart’s convincing critique of Rousseau in Hart (1992), 449–51.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Oppressing people is an example of such an action, and is deeply tied to taking up another’s evil as your good or another’s good as your evil. To do either is to oppress, and as Freire has pointed out, there is an objectification (loss of subjectivity) in both oppressors and oppressed when such actions occur. “Dehumanization,” he writes, “…marks not only those whose humanity has been stolen, but also…those who have stolen it” (Freire (1971), 28). To oppress, to put it in other terms, is to take up another’s evil as one’s good (or vice versa) and that in turn leads to an experience of one’s Self and the Other as less-than-persons—an experience which goes against the fundamental experience of one’s Self and the Other (which made the act of oppression possible in the first place).

    Google Scholar 

  20. Hart (1992), 450.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Frazer and Lacey (1993), 153.

    Google Scholar 

  22. See Carr (1986), 153–85. I have considered the role of narrative in the constitution of community and Self as well (Cf. Steeves (1994)).

    Google Scholar 

  23. See Hauerwas(1981).

    Google Scholar 

  24. Cf. Maclntyre(1984).

    Google Scholar 

  25. Cf. Walzer (1987). In this work, Walzer ponders whose interpretation “counts” based on the critics’ “distance” from the tradition. The problem is, of course, unnecessary, and I will say something about this shortly.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Rachels(1986), 144.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Hart (1992), 209.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Hart (1992), 211.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Husserl as quoted by Hart (1992), 248.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Husserl as quoted by Hart (1992), 372.

    Google Scholar 

  31. This is a particularly illuminating example because it might seem that if I am shopping at the mall as well, then there is a common agency. Nothing could be further from the truth, for even though we might be engaged in similar actions, we are not pursuing a common goal, but rather we have a goal in common. Indeed, my absence (both my physical absence and the absence of my will) would no doubt please most of the other shoppers. In Hart’s words, our being together is not out of a desire to be together, “not a result of social-communicative acts.” (Cf. Hart (1992), 249.)

    Google Scholar 

  32. See Sbragia(1992), 1.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Sbragia (1992), 5–6.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Miles Kahler, “The Survival of the State in European International Relations,” in Maier (1987), 300.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Sbragia(1992), 16.

    Google Scholar 

  36. See Oldenquist(1986).

    Google Scholar 

  37. Cf. Sandel (1982), 161–65.

    Google Scholar 

  38. See Hardin (1974), 38–43, 123–126.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Robert Nisbet, “The Problem of Community” in Daly (1994), 141–43.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Michael Sandel, “The Procedural Republic and the Unencumbered Self,” in Avineri and De-Shalit (1992), 28.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Quoted by Shirley Brice Heath in Resnick (1991), 122.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Shirley Brice Heath in Resnick (1991), 122.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Kohn (1986), 117–18.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Kohn(1986), 129.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Kohn (1986), 127.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Kohn(1986), 134.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Kemmis(1990), 117, 122, 118–19.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Berry (1977), 22. This observation about non-human life as neighbor will be important to keep in mind for chapter 6.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Bolívar(1971), 51.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Simon (1962), 65.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Simon(1962),66.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Simon(1962), 30.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Simon(1962), 125.

    Google Scholar 

  54. Simon(1962), 25.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1998 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Steeves, H.P. (1998). Phenomenological Communitarianism. In: Founding Community. Phaenomenologica, vol 143. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-5182-5_5

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-5182-5_5

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-010-6180-3

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-011-5182-5

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics