Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science ((BSPS,volume 126))

  • 248 Accesses

Abstract

European science has its origin in Greece. Rationalism, openness to new ideas, the willingness to learn from others, freedom from religious constraints and superstitious fears, flexibility of mind, critical attitudes to tradition, — here is a random list of characteristics said to be common to Greek science and to ours. We have much to thank the Greeks for. Still: the inheritance of Greece has also been a heavy burden on European science. For some of its important legacies to posterity had for many centuries a potently inhibitory effect on scientific thought and enquiry. I need mention only the survival throughout antiquity and the middle ages (almost, though not entirely, without opposition) of such powerful models in astronomy as that of the geocentric universe, or of the circular motions of the heavenly bodies; or of teleology in the biological sciences; or of certain Greek attitudes to work and to the translation of science into technology.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. DK 21 A 33.

    Google Scholar 

  2. DK 12A 10, 11 and 30 = [Plut. Strom. 2; Hippol. Ref. I. 6,6; Censorinus IV. 7; Plut. Symp. VIII. 8,4 p. 730E.

    Google Scholar 

  3. See W. K. C. Guthrie, A History of Greek Philosophy, II (Cambridge, 1965), pp. 398f.

    Google Scholar 

  4. DK 67 A7.

    Google Scholar 

  5. See Aristotle, de anima I.2, 403 b 31ff.; Lucretius II. 112ff.; Lactantius, de ira dei, 10, 9. Note that Lucretius uses such expressions as simulacrum and imago (loc. cit.). In any case, a good deal of what some modern historians of ancient science describe as remarkable anticipations of modern physical theories is really nothing of the sort. It would be well if historians kept in mind the salutary warning of a recent biographer of Einstein: ‘… the most difficult task in studying past science is to forget temporarily what came afterwards’ (A. Pais, Subtle is the Lord, The Science and the Life of Albert Einstein (Oxford and New York, 1982), p. 9).

    Google Scholar 

  6. See below and also A. Wasserstein, ‘Epicurean Science’ in Hermes, 106 (1978), pp. 484–494.

    Google Scholar 

  7. See A. Wasserstein, ‘Greek Scientific Thought’ in Proceedings of the Cambridge Philological Society, N.S. 8 (1962), pp. 51ff.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Simplicius, in Arist. de caelo, 492, 31ff.; G. Schiaparelli, ‘Le sfere omocentriche di Eudosso, di Callippo e di Aristotele’, in Pubblicazioni del R. Osservatorio di Brera in Milano, IX (1875); J. L. E. Dreyer, History of the Planetary Systems from Thales to Kepler (Cambridge, 1906), pp. 89ff.; O. Neugebauer, The Exact Sciences in Antiquity (New York, 1962), pp. 153f; D. R. Dicks, Early Greek Astronomy to Aristotle (London, 1970), pp. 176ff. (with more modern literature). The clearest exposition for the non-specialist reader (and the most easily accessible) is still that by Sir Thomas Heath in Aristarchus of Samos (Oxford, 1913), (reprinted 1959), pp. 193ff. (based on Schiaparelli and Dreyer).

    Google Scholar 

  9. Ptolemy, Almagest III. 4, Heiberg I. p. 232.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Republic, VII. 529–530.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Simplicius, in Arist. de caelo, p. 504, 17–20.

    Google Scholar 

  12. See Euclid IX. 20; and cf. A. Wasserstein, Economy and Elegance (Leicester, 1961), pp. 14 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  13. For the history of the generalisation see A. Wasserstein, ‘Theaetetus and the History of the Theory of Numbers’, Classical Quarterly, N.S. VIII (1958), pp. 165ff. For the proof see Euclid, X, App. 27 (ed. Heiberg-Stamatis).

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. See Guthrie, Guthrie, A History of Greek Philosophy, (above, note 2), I, p. 265, n. 1.

    Google Scholar 

  15. See T. L. Heath, A History of Greek Mathematics (Oxford, 1921), (repr. 1960), I, p. 71.

    MATH  Google Scholar 

  16. Proclus, Hypotyposes p. 150f (Halma).

    Google Scholar 

  17. See, e.g., J. Burnet, Early Greek Philosophy (1920), pp. 335f.; Kirk and Raven, op. cit., pp. 306 and 406; Guthrie, A History of Greek Philosophy, II, p. 392.

    Google Scholar 

  18. B. Farrington, Greek Science (Harmondsworth, 1944), p. 30.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Hippocrates, transl. W. H. S. Jones, Vol. 1 (Cambridge, Mass., 1984), Loeb Classical Library, pp. 13–15.

    Google Scholar 

  20. 297 b 18f.; cf. also 296 b 19f. The above is a paraphrase. A literal translation would present problems the solutions of which are irrelevant to our purpose. See W. K. C. Guthrie, transl., Aristotle, On the Heavens. (Cambridge, Mass., 1971), Loeb Classical Library, p. 244 note, and diagram on p. 245.

    Google Scholar 

  21. For the following see, in greater detail, A. Wasserstein, ‘Epicurean Science’ in Hermes, 106 (1978), pp. 484–494; and cf. Lucretius II. 216–293; Cicero, de finibus I. 6, 19; id., de fato 9, 18; 10, 22; 20, 46; id., de natura deorum 1, 25, 69; Plut., de sollen, an. 964 c; id., de an. procr. in Tim. Plat. 1015 c; Aetius 1, 12, 5; id., 1, 23, 4; Diog. Oen, 32, II–III (Chilton); Augustine, contra academicos 3, 23.

    Google Scholar 

  22. See Cicero, supra, note 29.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Cicero, de fato 10, 22–23; cf. also 9.18 and id., de natura deorum 1, 25, 69.

    Google Scholar 

  24. A. A. Long, Hellenistic Philosophy (London, 1974), p. 36.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1991 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Wasserstein, A. (1991). Hunches that did not come off: Some Problems in Greek Science. In: Unguru, S. (eds) Physics, Cosmology and Astronomy, 1300–1700: Tension and Accommodation. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol 126. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-3342-5_2

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-3342-5_2

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-010-5476-8

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-011-3342-5

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics