Skip to main content

The Content of Knowledge

  • Chapter
  • 124 Accesses

Part of the book series: The University of Western Ontario Series in Philosophy of Science ((WONS,volume 50))

Abstract

The history of the theory of knowledge from the Greeks through the 17th Century can be written as a history of attempts to construct an account of knowledge as certainty (i.e., infallibilism). This history might also be written from a variety of other points of view, for example, as the conquest of reason, as the accumulation of truth, and as the continuing quest for rationality, among other candidates. No particular view has a clear lien on accuracy. But the question here is not which of the many historical perspectives that there are is the correct one. Rather, the problem is how to choose among these perspectives. Despite what was said earlier against simple-minded wholesale categorizations of individual thinkers, we need to provide at least a working Solution to this problem because without a systematic rendering of the past we cannot employ contemporary categories of analysis to best advantage. As noted earlier, my purpose is not merely to explicate Galileo’s epistemological views, but to understand how those views contribute to our understanding of science. It is for this reason that I am making the effort to translate some of Galileo’s concerns into our modern idiom. And, as we have seen, he raises the issue of certainty himself fairly early. Thus, it is important to locate the issue of certainty on the historical screen, but only in broad and, we grant, not indelible strokes.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Think of the wealth of detail in James Joyce’s Ulysses — and then how much he left out.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Cf. I. B. Cohen [1985] for a provocative discussion of the develop-ment of the concept of a revolution in science.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Cf. Popkin [1979], Burnyeat [ 1983 ].

    Google Scholar 

  4. See Levi [1980]; Lewis [1946]; Kant [1964]; Pierce [1955].

    Google Scholar 

  5. For a thorough examination of the arguments on this issue see R. Almeder’s [1987].

    Google Scholar 

  6. This is not to say that there are no theories of knowledge in which absolute truth is down-played. Some recent examples of efforts in this direction are to be found in the work of Rescher [1973], Laudan [1978] and the present author [ 1981 ]. Essential to these programs is the abandonment of any attempt to see science and, hence, knowledge as in some sense marching toward some final theory or ultimate set of truths.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Even given Stillman Drake’s monumental efforts to document the details of Galileo’s scientific life, it is still not clear how Galileo came to put his theory of the tides together with his Reply to Ignoli, ultimately producing the Dialogue. At the risk of suggesting too much of a similarity between contemporary life and behavior pat-terns of scientists in Galileo’s time, it almost looks as if when ap-proached by the Church for something to show the outside world, Galileo reached into his bottom drawer and came up with lots of bits and pieces which had been resting down there finished for some time but which remained unpublished. He then got the idea of putting them together, a not uncommon practice among our more hard-pressed and overcommitted colleagues today. If there is a dif-ference it might be that today we would be content to publish a book of essays, while Galileo tried to make it all hang together.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Except for the arguments for the earth’s motion based on the variations in the sunspots, which, if Drake is correct, Galileo had not yet seen as significant.

    Google Scholar 

  9. See Drake [1984].

    Google Scholar 

  10. Galileo is not alone in his attacks on that distinction. See, for example, Cardinal Bellarmine’s Louvaine lectures [ 1985 ].

    Google Scholar 

  11. See Wallace [1984] for a thorough account of Aristotelian/Renais-sance principles of proof, and his [1981] for an account of reasoning ex suppositione in particular.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Cf. Laudan [1981].

    Google Scholar 

  13. Wallace notes that this is the only outright use of the expression ex suppositione in the Dialogue [1984, p. 310]

    Google Scholar 

  14. Anticipating in interesting ways Newton’s second rule, “Therefore to the same natural effects we must, as far as possible, assign the same causes.” (Newton [1974, Vol. 2, p. 398])

    Google Scholar 

  15. On this point McMullin even agrees.

    Google Scholar 

  16. See Pitt [1981].

    Google Scholar 

  17. Copernicus offers a feeble attempt at providing the required physical theory. But, a pale adaptation of Aristotelian mechanics, it was recognized as inadequate from the Start.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Koyre [1978] maintained that Galileo performed few if any experi-ments and these experimental results he refers to are falsified by Galileo’s own contemporaries. This is a typical Koyrean exaggera-tion. Thomas Settie has reenacted a number of Galileo’s experiments and performed them to accord with Galileo’s own reports. Koyre’s insistence on the lack of any real role for experimentation in Galileo’s method appears connected to his obsession with the idea that the Scientific Revolution is an intellectual revolt. The result of recent scholarship has shown Koyre’s view here to be very narrow; see, for example, Drake [1975], McLachlan [1973], Settie [ 1961 ].

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1992 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Pitt, J.C. (1992). The Content of Knowledge. In: Galileo, Human Knowledge, and the Book of Nature. The University of Western Ontario Series in Philosophy of Science, vol 50. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-2620-5_4

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-2620-5_4

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-010-5158-3

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-011-2620-5

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics