Skip to main content

Mathematics as a Transcendental Science

  • Chapter
Phenomenology and the Formal Sciences

Part of the book series: Contributions to Phenomenology ((CTPH,volume 8))

Abstract

We are hearing a great deal at this conference about phenomenology and its connection with ontology, logic and mathematics. I want to put some of this into historical perspective by talking about Kant and Brouwer, two thinkers who are known for their analyses of consciousness, and for taking these analyses from phenomenology to the ontology, and ultimately to the logic of ordinary empirical discourse and of mathematics. Specifically I want to use the case studies of Kant and Brouwer in order to precisely formulate just how one can connect phenomenology with ontology, and, once that connection is made, how it in turn effects matters of logic. For it seems to me that these connections are not always well understood in contemporary discussions of Kant and Brouwer, and of these issues in general.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. See for instance Brouwer’s”Discours Final” in Les Methodes Formelles en Axiomatique”, Colloque CNRS, Paris, 1950, p. 75, (reprinted in Brouwer’s Collected Works, v. 1, A. Heyting (ed.) North Holland, 1975, p. 503).

    Google Scholar 

  2. See Chapter II of Brouwer’s Ph. D. thesis, Over de grondslagen der wiskunde, Amsterdam, 1907, (translated as “On the foundations of mathematics”, in Collected Works, I, pp. 11–101); Brouwer’s innaugural lecture”Hei wezen der meetkunde”, Amsterdam, 1909, (translated as “The nature of geometry” in Collected Works, I, pp. 112–120); and “Intuitionism and Formalism”, Bull. Amer. Math. Soc., v. 20, 1913, pp. 81–96, (reprinted in Collected Works, I, pp. 123–138).

    Google Scholar 

  3. A. Heyting,”Die formalen Regeln der intuitionistischen Logik”, Sitzungsber. preuss. Akad. Wiss., 1930, pp. 42–56.

    Google Scholar 

  4. See for instance G. Brittan Kant’s Theory of Science, Princeton University Press, 1978; and C. Posy, “Dancing to the Antinomy”, Amer. Phil. Quart., v. 20, 1983, pp. 81–94.

    Google Scholar 

  5. See Critique of Pure Reason, A105.

    Google Scholar 

  6. See Husserl’s Cartesian Meditations, 53–54.

    Google Scholar 

  7. This is discernable in Brouwer’s emphasis on the notion of “repeatable phenomena” in”De onbetrouwbaarheid der logische principes”, Tijdschrift voor wijsbegeerte, 2, 1908, pp. 152—158, (translated as “The unreliability of the logical principles in” in Collected Works, I, pp. 107–112); and in the notions of “iterative complexes” and “causal sequences” in his “Consciousness, Philosophy and Mathematics”, in Proc. of 10th. Internat Cong, of Phil”, Amsterdam, 1948, pp. 1235–1249, (reprinted in Collected Works, I, pp. 480–494).

    Google Scholar 

  8. See for instance Brouwer’s summaries in “Historical Background, Principles and Methods of Intuitionism”, in S. African J. Sci., v. 49, 1952, pp. 139–146 (reprinted in Collected Works, I pp. 508—515); and “Points and Spaces”, Canad. J. Math., v. 6, 1954, pp. 1—17, (reprinted in Collected Works, I pp. 522–538).

    Google Scholar 

  9. See A 524/B 552 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  10. See C. Posy, “Brittanic and Kantian Objects”, in New Essays on Kant, B. den Ouden (ed.), Peter Lang Publishing Co., 1987.

    Google Scholar 

  11. See A 792/B 820.

    Google Scholar 

  12. I. e., — A is true if and only if A is false, (A&B) is true if and only if A and B are, (AvB) is true if and only if A is or B is, etc.

    Google Scholar 

  13. See S. Kleene,”Introduction to Metamathematics”, van Nostrand, 1952.

    Google Scholar 

  14. See, e. g., “The Philosophical Basis of Intuitionistic Logic”, in Truth and Other Enigmas, Harvard University Press, 1978, pp. 215–247.

    Google Scholar 

  15. In my review of Dummett’s Elements of Intuitionism in History and Philosophy of Logic, v. 2, 1981, I pointed out that this assumption of Heyting’s and Dummett’s is not universally shared and has mixed textual evidence.

    Google Scholar 

  16. See for instance Brouwer’s”De non-aequivalentie van de constructieve en de negatieve orderelatie in het continuum”, Indag. math., v. 11, 1949, pp. 37–39, (translated as “The non-equivalence of the constructive and the negative order relation on the continuum” in Collected works, I pp. 495–496); and chapter 1 of Brouwer’s [1946] Cambridge Lectures on Intuitionism, D. van Dalen (ed.), Cambridge University Press, 1981. In “On Brouwer’s Definition of Unextendable Order” (History and Philosophy of Logic, v. 1, 1980) I argued that this tensed notion of truth is helpful in interpreting Brouwer’s earlier work as well.

    Google Scholar 

  17. See, for instance,”De onbetrouwbaarheid der logische principes” (details in note 7) and”Intuitionistische Betrachtungen über den Formalismus”, Sitzber. preuss. Akad. Wiss., 1928, pp. 48—52, (reprinted in Collected Works, I pp. 409–414).

    Google Scholar 

  18. See”De onbetrouwbaarheid der logische principes” (details in note 7).

    Google Scholar 

  19. See A 480–81/B 508–9.

    Google Scholar 

  20. See for instance Dummett’s “Realism” in Truth and Other Enigmas, pp. 145–165.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Actually it is fair to say that for both Kant and Brouwer there is a context in which the empirical project is itself subsidiary to more primary “practical” concerns. This is a well known thesis in Kant interpretation. See R. Kroner, Kant’s Weltanschauung, (Tübingen, 1914; translated by J. E. Smith, Chicago, 1956) for a classic statement of this thesis. In Brouwer’s case note the primacy of “cunning”, the “move from means to end” and the general pragmatic attitude in the works cited in notes 1,2 and 7.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1991 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Posy, C.J. (1991). Mathematics as a Transcendental Science. In: Seebohm, T.M., Føllesdal, D., Mohanty, J.N. (eds) Phenomenology and the Formal Sciences. Contributions to Phenomenology, vol 8. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-2580-2_8

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-2580-2_8

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-010-5138-5

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-011-2580-2

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics