Skip to main content

Chemistry and Hegel’s Logic

  • Chapter
Hegel and Newtonianism

Abstract

When lecturing on elective affinity, Hegel referred to John Dalton’s theory of atomic weights. He observed that, although Dalton had been the first to recognize that chemical elements combine according to definite proportions, “he enveloped his determinations in the worst form of atomistic metaphysics”.1 This rejection of atomic theory did not appear unannounced, for in the remark to paragraph 298 of the Philosophy of Nature, he points out that when he talks about material parts he does not mean atoms or molecules. Since atoms and molecules are understood to be separated and subsisting on their own, they cannot be continuous; if there is to be continuity, two parts must subsist in the same place.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 259.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 329.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 329.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Hegel Encyclopedia § 333 Addition; tr. Petry II.213,10f.; tr. Miller p. 263.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Hegel Encyclopedia § 98; tr. Wallace (1895) pp. 181-185; tr. Geraets etc. (1991) pp. 155-157. Compare Hegel GW (WL) 11.93; 21.153-155; tr. Miller pp. 165-167.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Hegel Encyclopedia §§ 326–336; tr. Petry II.178-222; tr. Miller pp. 232-272.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Hegel Encyclopedia §§ 200–203; tr. Wallace (1892) pp. 341-343; tr. Geraets etc. (1991) pp. 277-279. See also Hegel GW (WL) 12.148-153; tr. Miller pp. 727-733.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Hegel GW (WL) 12.152,7-20; tr. Miller p. 731.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Hegel Encyclopedia § 329 Addition; tr. Petry II.190,32; tr. Miller p. 243.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Hegel GW (WL) 12.148,28-149,2; tr. Miller p. 727.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Hegel GW (WL) 12.150,7-9; tr. Miller p. 729.

    Google Scholar 

  9. For the motif of self-reference as central to the logic see Halper, E. 1981.

    Google Scholar 

  10. This explication of the text is based on the larger Logic.

    Google Scholar 

  11. For an extended discussion of Hegel’s theory of syllogism, see Burbidge, J. 1981, pp. 158-192.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Hegel Encyclopedia § 263; tr. Petry I.244; tr. Miller p. 47.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Hegel Encyclopedia § 325; tr. Petry II.177; tr. Miller p. 232.

    Google Scholar 

  14. For this comparison I have relied on the texts provided in von Engelhardt, D. 1976, pp. 138ff.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Michael John Petry

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1993 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Burbidge, J.W. (1993). Chemistry and Hegel’s Logic. In: Petry, M.J. (eds) Hegel and Newtonianism. Archives Internationales D’Histoire Des Idées / International Archives of the History of Ideas, vol 136. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-1662-6_38

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-1662-6_38

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-010-4726-5

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-011-1662-6

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics