Skip to main content

The Concept of Force in Eighteenth-Century Mechanics

  • Chapter
Hegel and Newtonianism

Abstract

If one wanted to characterize the general scientific approach of the eighteenth-century by means of a single concept, there would be much to be said for selecting the notion of force. Newton’s Principia (1687) had unified the laws of terrestrial mechanics and planetary motion by propounding a mathematical conception of force applicable in principle within every field of natural philosophy. Discussion of the universal principles and characteristic quantities of motion had entered a new stage as a result of the publication of this book. The plan to extend the application of the conception of mechanical force to the fields of optics and chemistry was explicitly formulated by Newton in his Opticks (1704), and developed into what was to become the general paradigm of Newtonian physics.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 259.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 329.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 329.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Freind and Keill were the most important Newtonians in Britain at that time. See Cassirer, 1974, II, pp. 401ff., 421ff.; cf. Rosenberger, 1895, pp. 342ff., 359ff., Guerlac, 1981, pp. 41-74.

    Google Scholar 

  2. For the first reactions to Newton’s physics in France, see Rosenberger, 1895, pp. 354ff.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Westfall, 1977, pp. 65-81.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Westfall, 1977, pp. 82-104.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Newton, 1988, p. 75; Newton, 1988, p. 6; Böhme, 1977, p. 251.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Westfall, 1972, pp. 184-189.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Cf. Jammer, 1962, pp. 116ff.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Cohen, 1978, p. 166.

    Google Scholar 

  9. For example: Newton Principia bk. 3, prop. 4, theor. 4, scholium; bk. 3, prop. 5, theor. 5, scholium.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Cohen, 1978, p. 48.

    Google Scholar 

  11. See Newton’s use of the term centrifugal in the Principia bk. 1, prop. 4, theor. 4, scholium, the interpretation of this provided by Westfall, 1977, pp. 145-148, and the correct description of the force in Baumgartner, 1829, § 252, p. 193. Böhme, 1988, brings out the importance of the concept of the centrifugal force in Newton’s development of hydrodynamics: see the Principia bk. 2, sect. 5, prop. 23, theor. 18; sect. 7, prop. 33; sect. 7, prop. 33, cor. 3; sect. 7, prop. 33, cor. 6: bk. 3, prop. 4, theor. 4, scholium; prop. 19, prob. 3. In all these cases, Newton treats the centrifugal force as having a component opposed to the centripetal force. Elsewhere, he maintains that the centripetal becomes a centrifugal force when the path changes from a parabola to a hyperbola: bk. 1, prop. 10, prob. 5, scholium; prop. 12, prob. 7.

    Google Scholar 

  12. f = ma.

    Google Scholar 

  13. The new co-ordinates may be x;w is the rotating velocity: f eff = f-2m(w · dx/dt)-mw(w · x). Cf. Goldstein, 1963, p. 149.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Newton Principia, law 2.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Newton Principia, bk. 3, rule 3.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Newton Principia, def. 3.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Wolff, 1978, pp. 16ff., 320ff. — but Wolff did not always succeed in describing centrifugal force in a correct way (pp. 321, 328).

    Google Scholar 

  18. Newton seems to adopt the main features of Descartes’ principle of inertia from the second law stated in Descartes, 1644, II. Part, § 39.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Cardwell, 1966, pp. 209-224.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Kant, 1746, discusses the notion of force in the Leibnizian tradition.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Cf. Freudenthal, 1982, pp. 46ff., 61ff.

    Google Scholar 

  22. See also Bernoulli, Joh. 1742, chap. V, §§ 2, 3, Opera omnia III, p. 35f.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Leibniz, 1982, p. 13 (1695);’ s Gravesande tried to confirm this by experiments:’ s Gravesande, 1748, pp. xii, xx, xxvf., 229ff., 245ff., and Musschenbroek, 17412. Musschenbroek argued that even a body which is at rest can transfer motion to another body (§ 196, p. 78).

    Google Scholar 

  24. Here Leibniz, 1982, refers to Newton’s Principia (1687), from which it can be inferred that the various notions of force are being respected.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Leibniz, 1982, p. 15.

    Google Scholar 

  26. The dicussion concerning the impenetrability of matter deserves to be dealt with in more detail. The problem was discussed by Euler, 1773, vol. 1 and, for example, by Hamberger, 1741, §§ 35ff., who says that the impenetrability of matter, as well as its resistence, are induced by the vis insita, which enables the body to move in any direction; § 28 of this work is concerned with the vis inertiae.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Cf. Kleinert, 1974.

    Google Scholar 

  28. In France: Voltaire, 1738; Algarotti, 1745; Fontenelle, 1780; Pluche, 1753ff.; Regnault, 1729-1750; Clairaut, 1747, were important. In Britain: Pemberton, 1728, described planetary motion in an orthodox Newtonian manner, without mentioning centrifugal force; another common description derived from Martin, 1778; Martin’s book was used by Hegel: cf. Neuser, W. 1990b; Hegel DOP; cf. Encyclopedia §§ 245-271; tr. Petry I, 1970. In Germany: Erxleben, 17874 — the main source of the physical knowledge of the late Kant; Euler, 1773 ff., vol. 1. Algarotti’s, Pluche’s and Fontenelle’s books were written in Italian or French and then translated into German, and do not give a very precise account of Newton’s theory of planetary motion. Erxleben sometimes conceives of centrifugal force in the right way (§§ 56, 659), sometimes not (§ 660). Martin confused centrifugal force with the force of inertia. Euler, 1773 ff., 1, provides a clear and instructive discussion of the different aspects of Newtonian and Leibnizian physics.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Borzeszkowski and Wahsner, 1978, pp. 19-57.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Voltaire, 1745, vol. 31, pp. 222-233; Voltaire 1739.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Maupertuis corrected Voltaire’s book before it was published.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Voltaire, 1745, 31, pp. 227-231.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Châtellet, 1740, §§ 373-376. It is evident from her French translation of Newton’s Principia that she was aware that Newton’s centrifugal force is perpendicular to the tangent of the circle; cf. Châtellet, 1756, I, p. 57; II, p. 15; II, p. 35.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Châtellet, 1740, § 357.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Winkler, 1754, p. 8, § 92.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Gehler, 1787, vol. 1, pp. 487ff; 494; cf. 1787, vol. 5, p. 194 below. In modern textbooks of experimental physics one still finds this interpretation: Gerthsen and Kneser, 1969, p. 16; Westphal, 1970, p. 68. Bergmann and Schäfer, 1970, vol. 1, pp. 115ff.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Gehler, 1787, vol. 1, p. 505.

    Google Scholar 

  38. MacLaurin, 1748, p. 310.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Martin, 1778.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Greenberg, 1986, pp. 59-78.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Maupertuis, 1753, pp. 38-42; cf. Lagrange, 1797.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Zedler, 1737, unwittingly provides an instructive example of the confusion of Newtonian and Leibnizian physics in the article on force; he describes all types of forces as dead or living, but refers only to Newton’s force of inertia (pp. 1681, 1691ff., 1691ff.), not to that of Leibniz; cf. Iltis, 1971, pp. 21-35; Laudan, 1968, pp. 131-143.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Mach, 1933, pp. 39ff.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Cf. Goldstein, 1963, eh. IX.

    Google Scholar 

  45. D’Alembert, 1743, p. 14.

    Google Scholar 

  46. D’Alembert, 1743, pp. 33-34.

    Google Scholar 

  47. D’Alembert, 1743, p. 83.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Cf. Neuser, 1989, pp. 27-40; Neuser, 1986, pp. 30ff.; cf. Cassirer, 1974, II, pp. 401ff., 421ff.

    Google Scholar 

  49. D’Alembert, 1743, p. 16.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Goldstein, 1963, p. 14.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Hankins, 1967, pp. 43-65.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Philosophische Gesellschaft an der Universität zu Wien 1899, p. 115.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Boscovich, 1758, pp. xii, xiv, xvi, 35.

    Google Scholar 

  54. Gren, 1788, provides an excellent discussion of these problems, cf. Adickes, 1924, vol. 1, p. 171.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Franklin, 1758, pp. 70ff.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Helmholtz, 1983, p. 16.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Michael John Petry

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1993 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Neuser, W. (1993). The Concept of Force in Eighteenth-Century Mechanics. In: Petry, M.J. (eds) Hegel and Newtonianism. Archives Internationales D’Histoire Des Idées / International Archives of the History of Ideas, vol 136. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-1662-6_26

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-1662-6_26

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-010-4726-5

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-011-1662-6

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics