Skip to main content

The Dialectical Structure of Zeno’s Arguments

  • Chapter
Hegel and Newtonianism

Abstract

Although no evidence of a logical fallacy was ever produced, philosophers and logicians of the nineteenth century shared the conviction that Zeno’s arguments against motion were simply eristic paralogisms. Hegel was an exception. He was already an exception by the simple fact of taking the arguments seriously: he argues — “Zeno’s dialectics of matter is, up to this day, unrefuted”. It is still unrefuted and irrefutable. But Hegel was singular too in considering the arguments — in accordance with a testimony of Aristotle on Zeno as the inventor of dialectic — as a relevant manifestation of dialectical reasoning: “Zeno’s specificity is the dialectics”. It should however be admitted that Hegel’s comments are rather conjectural, and they are certainly eclipsed by confusing obscurities, opening a rich source of misinterpretations, which few have been able to resist. In the present paper an attempt is made to provide a new interpretation of the arguments in the hope that this will contribute to making their hidden dialectical structure more transparent.

The present paper is part of the research project Antike in der Moderne sponsored by the Volkswagen Stiftung, Hanover. For more details, concerning the mathematical passages of the present paper, see my article quoted in the bibliography.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 259.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 329.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 329.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Aristotle, Anal. prior. 65b18; Hegel, Jub. 17, pp. 318, 328; Aristotle, Frg. 65; Plato, Parmenides 127A.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Arist., Phys. 239b19-20.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Simplicius, In Arist. physicorum p. 1013; Saadia Gaon, The Book of Beliefs p. 45, I 1.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Arist., Phys. 262a3.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Ibid. 204a6-7, 206a22.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Ibid. 261a36.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Plato, Parmenides 165AD.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Arist., Phys. 263a5–11; De lineis insec. 969a31-34; also ibid. 968a25-b4.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Plato, Parm. 135E–136A; see also Aristotle, Top. 158al5-17.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Spinoza, Epist. xii, 20 April 1663.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Arist., de lin. insec. 971a10-12, 972al2.

    Google Scholar 

  12. The Elements,bk. xii props. 2, 5, 10-12, 18. In an impressive number of books and papers, published in the last twenty years, Prof. A. Szabó recurrently repeats the quite astonishing assertion, that axion 8 of “the greater and the part” is nowhere used in the Elements. Under these circumstances, the intention of Euclid, in listing axiom 8 at the beginning of the Elements, could have been nothing else — according to Szabó — than to provide a refutation of Zeno’s Arguments, since — as the Author believes — the axiom of “the whole and the part” is inconsistent with Zeno.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Elem. ii 10.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Plato, Politikos 266AB.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Elem. ii 9.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Elem. ii 9 and 10; Proclus, In rem publ. ii 27.

    Google Scholar 

  17. De lin. insec. 968b19.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Euclid Elements,bk. x theor. 2.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Arist, Anal, prior. 65bl6–22.

    Google Scholar 

  20. For instance in Polit. 287C, Laws. 820A.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Plato, Rep. 534D. The evidence for the mathematical relevance of the passage was provided by Eva Sachs, op. cit.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Ilias xxii 157; Arist., Poetica 1460al3-25, b26; Plato, Phaedrus 266B. The Tortoise is a contrivance of Simplicius (in Phys. 1014-1015). A felicitous cast of the parts: substituting the ludicrous reptile for Hector, the defeat of “the world-famous tragical hero of speed” (cf. Arist. Phys. 239b24-25) could since then be successfully produced on the stage according to the plot of a metaphysical chelonomachy.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Arist., Phys. 239bl8–19.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Arist., Phys. 204a7, b4; 206al5; 207b29.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Arist., Phys 239bl5–16.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Plato, Parm 140E–142A; 151E-157B.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Plato, Polit. 270B–271C.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Plato, Parm. 152B.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Iliad xxii, 157–158; Joyce, Ulysses p. 794; Plato, Apology 39AB.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Arist, Metaph. 1087b7–18.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Plato, Parm. 155D, 160CD.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Ibid. 141A, 150C-151C.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Ibid 165A.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Arist., Metaph. 1081a25, 1083b31-32, 1087b5-18.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Plato, Farm. 157D.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Ibid. 151B, 147C.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Ibid. 155E–156A.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Ibid. Polit. 283C-284A; Arist., Metaph. 1087bl8.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Plato, Farm. 161CD, 153C.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Ibid. 156B–157D, 159C.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Ibid. 156D.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Ibid. 157C, 158B.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Ibid. 153C.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Plato, Philebus 14C–16C, 24A. 26D.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Georg Cantor, op. cit., p. 204.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Plato, Polit. 283C–284A.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Parmenides, Frg. 815-16; see Diels-Kranz, op. cit., vol. i, p. 236. Plato, Parm. 157A; 137B.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Plato, Rep. 546C, Meno 83C.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Proclus, In rem. publ. ii 27.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Plato, Theait. 196A.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Imm. Kant, The Critique of Pure Reason, Introduction v 1 (Critik d. r. Vernunft, Riga 1787, p. 15).

    Google Scholar 

  52. Plato, Soph. 254A; Aristotle, Phys. 208b26-27.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Plato, Polit. 287C.

    Google Scholar 

  54. Plato, Parm. 140BD.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Ibid. 156E–157A, 156DE.

    Google Scholar 

  56. The current translation: “On irrational lines and solids”, or “atoms”, has no mathematical sense whatever. The meaning of the Greek term is unambiguous: compact, filled, without holes.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Georg Cantor, op. cit. pp. 148, 182-184, 195-199.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Michael John Petry

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1993 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Toth, I. (1993). The Dialectical Structure of Zeno’s Arguments. In: Petry, M.J. (eds) Hegel and Newtonianism. Archives Internationales D’Histoire Des Idées / International Archives of the History of Ideas, vol 136. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-1662-6_15

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-1662-6_15

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-010-4726-5

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-011-1662-6

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics