Skip to main content

Problems of Theoretical Physics in the Second Half of Nineteenth Century

  • Chapter
A History of the Ideas of Theoretical Physics

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science ((BSPS,volume 213))

  • 1209 Accesses

Abstract

Many traditional histories fail to point out that J.C. Maxwell (1831–1879) was innovative not only in his new field theory of electricity and magnetism, but also in his idea of a physical theory.1

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Albert Einstein clearly recognised in various passages the revolutionary import of Maxwell’s theory (Einstein [1949] c) 33).

    Google Scholar 

  2. A clear understanding of Maxwell’s revolutionary view of the relationship between mathematics and physics can be grasped by a comparison between his and Thomson’s views as underlined by Smith and Wise. Thomson went out to slay the nihilist infidels of mathematical as opposed to physical ideas (Smith & Wise [1989] 445).

    Google Scholar 

  3. Maxwell [1855] 187.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Maxwell [1855] 208

    Google Scholar 

  5. Maxwell [1855] 208

    Google Scholar 

  6. D’Agostino [1968].

    Google Scholar 

  7. Boltzmann, “On the development of methods of theoretical physics” [1892], in Boltzmann [1974] 77–100, 89.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Poincaré [1890], Introduction, p. IV.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Maxwell [1891] [1954].

    Google Scholar 

  10. Maxwell [1891] [1954] Part IV, Chap. V, § 553, 199.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Maxwell [1891] [1954] Part IV § 554, 199.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Maxwell [1891] [1954] Part IV, Chap. XXI, § 818.

    Google Scholar 

  13. D’Agostino [1968] b.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Maxwell [1891] [1954] Part IV,, Chap. V, § 554, 209. In his review paper, dealing extensively with Maxwell’s dynamical ideas, Norton Wise refers to G.G. Stokes’ distinction between “mechanical” and “dynamical” theories, the latter consisting in a methods that do not require the physicist “to assume either that the ether does or that it does not consist of distinct particles” (Wise [1992] 186).

    Google Scholar 

  15. Buchwald [1985], XII. As remarked by Buchwald, historians, physicists and philosophers used to interpret Maxwell’s method as a method mainly based on analogies, thus missing what was typical in Maxwell’s DA.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Maxwell [1891] [1954] Part IV, Chap. IV, § 552, 198.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Maxwell [189]) [1954] Part IV, Chap. V, § 567, 200.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Maxwell [1891] [1954] Part IV, Chap. IX, § 604, 247. According to Buchwald, the same ideas were shared by the Maxwellian, the physicists who pursued Maxwell’s approach (Buchwald [1985] 96 ff.).

    Google Scholar 

  19. Buchwald [198]) 27–33, 37–40, 47.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Maxwell [1954] a), Vol.2, 362.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Maxwell, “On the Dynamical Evidence of the Molecular Constitution of Bodies”, in: Maxwell [1954] a), Vol. 2, 418.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Maxwell, “Atom”, in The Encyclopaedia Britannica, and in Maxwell [1954] a), 445–84.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Maxwell [1954] a) 470–471.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Maxwell [1954] a) 471.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Maxwell [1954] a) Vol. 2, 215–229.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Maxwell [1954] a) Vol. 2, 223–224.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Maxwell [1954] a) Vol. 2, 471.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Maxwell, “On Stresses in Rarefied Gases arising from Inequalities in Temperature”, Maxwell [1954] a) Vol. 2, 681–712. Maxwell died in November of the same year.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Maxwell, Appendix to “On stresses in Rarefied Gases”, added in May 1879, cited in: Maxwell [1954] a) Vol. 2, 703–712, 704.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Maxwell, “On Stresses in Rarefied Gases Arising from Inequalities in Temperature”, Maxwell [1954] a) Vol. 2, 681–712, 681.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Maxwell [1877], Maxwell [undated] Dover Publ.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Maxwell [undated] 122.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Maxwell [undated] Dover Publ, 122.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Maxwell [undated] Dover Publ., 122.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Heimholte [1878]; Helmholtz [1977].

    Google Scholar 

  36. Cappelletti [1976].

    Google Scholar 

  37. Helmholtz [1977] 118.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Helmholtz [1977] 119.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Helmholtz [1977] 122.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Helmholtz [1977] 122.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Helmholtz [1977] 118, 119.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Helmholtz [1977] 162.

    Google Scholar 

  43. For Helmholtz the general form is that schema devoid of any content which he declared “to be the true form of intuition, in respect of which Kant’s doctrine of the’ a-priori is to be upheld”; (M. Schlick, notes to Hermann von Helmholtz Epistemologica Writings, in: Helmholtz [1977] 172, note 33).

    Google Scholar 

  44. Helmholtz [1977] 162.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Helmholtz [1977], appendix n 3, 163.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Helmholtz [1977] 117.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Helmholtz [1977] 141.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Helmholtz [1977] 141.

    Google Scholar 

  49. M. Schlick, notes to Hermann von Helmholtz Epistemological Writings, in: Helmholtz [1977] 172.

    Google Scholar 

  50. D’Agostino [1990] 391.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Hertz [1894], Hertz [1956] Author’s Preface (pages not numbered).

    Google Scholar 

  52. Hertz [1956] 1.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Hertz [1956] 2.

    Google Scholar 

  54. Hertz [1956] 25.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Hertz [1956] 2.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Hertz [1956] 23.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Hertz [1956] 45.

    Google Scholar 

  58. Hertz [1956] 45.

    Google Scholar 

  59. Hertz [1891], Hertz [196]).

    Google Scholar 

  60. D’Agostino [1993] a).

    Google Scholar 

  61. Boltzmann, “On the Fundamental Principles and Equations of Mechanics” (1899), in: Boltzmann [1974] 119.

    Google Scholar 

  62. D’Agostino [1989].

    Google Scholar 

  63. Hertz, “The Forces of electric Oscillations”, in: Hertz [1962] 138.

    Google Scholar 

  64. The abolition of sources and of the classical concept of the force-source connection was certainly a paradigm shift of the utmost significance, as can be argued by the resistance it met among traditional physicists. As an example of this resistance, even at a later date, I like to quote Max Laue’s objection to Einstein’s equivalence principle in 1911, when have argues that a gravitational field produced by accelerating frames cannot be real since it has no masses as its sources; in: Einstein, “Dialog über Einvände gegen die Relativität Theorie”, Die Natürwis 6 [1918] 700. Quoted in: Norton [1985]. See also: D’Agostino [1993] a).

    ADS  Google Scholar 

  65. D’Agostino [1990].

    Google Scholar 

  66. Hertz [1962] 159.

    Google Scholar 

  67. Hertz [1962] 3. On this point, see also: Helmholtz’s Preface to Hertz [1956] xi.

    Google Scholar 

  68. Hertz [1962] 197.

    Google Scholar 

  69. Hertz [1962] 197. Notice that Hertz uses correctness, not truth, concerning the probation value of an experimental confirmation of a theory.

    Google Scholar 

  70. Hertz [1962] 197. This conception of the theory-experiment relationship was to be named later as the Duhem-Quine hypothesis.

    Google Scholar 

  71. Hertz “On Electromagnetic Waves in Air and their Reflections”, in: Hertz [1962] 136

    Google Scholar 

  72. Hertz, “The forces of Electric Oscillations Treated According to Maxwell’s Theory”, in: Hertz [1962] 159. Poincaré argued that Hertz’s experiments were not crucial for Maxwell’s theory. The French scientist believed that a true theory should be crucially tested by an experiment. On this point: D’Agostino [1986].

    Google Scholar 

  73. Mach [1926] 2.

    Google Scholar 

  74. Helmholtz [1878] 170.

    Google Scholar 

  75. Mach, Analyse der Empfindungen, in: Schlick’s notes to Helmholtz (1878) 177.

    Google Scholar 

  76. Helmholtz [1878] 172.

    Google Scholar 

  77. Mach [1894]; Mach [1943] 241.

    Google Scholar 

  78. Mach [1943] 253.

    Google Scholar 

  79. Mach [1943] 253.

    Google Scholar 

  80. Mach [1943] 248.

    Google Scholar 

  81. Mach [1943] 248.

    Google Scholar 

  82. Mach [1943] 177.

    Google Scholar 

  83. Mach [1943] 253.

    Google Scholar 

  84. Cassirer [1950] 84.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2000 Kluwer Academic Publishers

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

D’Agostino, S. (2000). Problems of Theoretical Physics in the Second Half of Nineteenth Century. In: A History of the Ideas of Theoretical Physics. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol 213. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-9034-6_4

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-9034-6_4

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-1-4020-0244-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-010-9034-6

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics