Skip to main content

Reply to Hilary Putnam’s ‘An Examination of Grünbaum’s Philosophy of Geometry’

  • Chapter
Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science ((BSPS,volume 5))

Abstract

Referring to my philosophical account of physical geometry and chronometry, H. Putnam1 says (p. 211): “Grünbaum has in my opinion failed to give a true picture of one of the greatest scientific advances of all time.” I have not found one single argument in Putnam’s 50 pages that could serve to sustain this judgment. Nay, reflection on fundamental mathematical and physical errors on which he rests much of his case has enabled me to uncover substantial new support for my position from the general theory of relativity and from elsewhere in physics.

I wish to thank my physicist colleague Allen I. Janis for invaluable help with points and examples in Sections 2, 8 and 9, and I am likewise indebted to Wesley C. Salmon for discussions relating to the interpretation of Putnam’s views. By prior arrangement, a slightly different version of this paper will appear as part of the author’s book Geometry and Chronometry in Philosophical Perspective, to be published in 1968 by the University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, Minn. I am most grateful to Hilary Putnam for having written the essay to which the present paper is a response; his work has been a valuable stimulus to me to clarify my views both to others and to myself. Critical severity is linked here with friendly respect.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Bibliography

  1. Adler, R., Bazin, M., and Schiffer, M. (eds.), Introduction to General Relativity, McGraw Hill Book Company, New York, 1965.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Bergmann, P., ‘The General Theory of Relativity’, in Handbuch der Physik, Vol. IV (ed. by S. Flügge), Springer Verlag, Berlin, 1962, pp. 203–272.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Bergmann, P., Introduction to the Theory of Relativity, Prentice-Hall, Inc., New York, 1946.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Clifford, W. K., The Common Sense of the Exact Sciences, Dover Publications, Inc., New York, 1955.

    Google Scholar 

  5. d’Abro, A., The Evolution of Scientific Thought From Newton to Einstein, Dover Publications, Inc., New York, 1950.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Dicke, R. H., The Theoretical Significance of Experimental Relativity, Gordon and Breach, New York, 1964.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Eddington, A. S., ‘The Cosmological Controversy’, Science Progress 34 (1939) 225–236.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Eddington, A. S., The Mathematical Theory of Relativity, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1952.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Eddington, A. S., Space, Time and Gravitation, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1953.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Einstein, A., ‘The Foundations of the General Theory of Relativity’, in The Principle of Relativity, A Collection of Original Memoirs, Dover Publications, Inc., New York, 1952, pp. 109–164.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Einstein, A., ‘Geometry and Experience’, in Readings in the Philosophy of Science (ed. by H. Feigl and M. Brodbeck), Appleton-Century-Crofts, Inc., New York, 1953, pp. 189–194.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Einstein, A., ‘On the Electrodynamics of Moving Bodies’, in The Principle of Relativity, A Collection of Original Memoirs, Dover Publications, Inc., New York, 1952, pp. 35–65.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Einstein, A., ‘Prinzipielles zur allgemeinen Relativitätstheorie’, Annalen der Physik 55 (1918) 241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  14. Einstein, A., ‘Reply to Criticisms’, in Albert Einstein: Philosopher-Scientist (ed. by P. A. Schilpp), The Library of Living Philosophers, Evanston, 1949, pp. 665–688.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Fine, A., ‘Physical Geometry and Physical Laws’, Philosophy of Science 31 (1964) 156–162.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  16. Fock, V., The Theory of Space, Time and Gravitation, 2nd revised edition, The Macmillan Company, New York, 1964.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Grünbaum, A., ‘A Consistent Conception of the Extended Linear Continuum as an Aggregate of Unextended Elements’, Philosophy of Science 19 (1952) 288–306.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. Grünbaum, A., ‘The Denial of Absolute Space and the Hypothesis of a Universal Nocturnal Expansion’, The Australasian Journal of Philosophy 45 (1967) 61–91.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  19. Grünbaum, A., Epilogue for P. W. Bridgman’s A Sophisticate’s Primer of Relativity, Wesleyan University Press, Middletown, 1962, pp. 165–191.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Grünbaum, A., ‘The Falsifiability of a Component of a Theoretical System’, in Mind, Matter, and Method: Essays in Philosophy and Science in Honor of Herbert Feigl (ed. by P. K. Feyerabend and G. Maxwell), University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, 1966.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Grünbaum, A., ‘The Falsifiability of Theories: Total or Partial? A Contemporary Evaluation of the Duhem-Quine Thesis’, Synthese 14 (1962) 17–34.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  22. Grünbaum, A., ‘The Genesis of the Special Theory of Relativity’, in Current Issues in the Philosophy of Science (ed. by H. Feigl and G. Maxwell), Holt, Rinehart and Winston, New York, 1961, pp. 43–53.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Grünbaum, A., ‘Logical and Philosophical Foundations of the Special Theory of Relativity’, in Philosophy of Science (ed. by A. Danto and S. Morgenbesser), Meridian Books, Inc., New York, 1960, pp. 399–434.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Grünbaum, A., ‘Modern Science and Refutation of the Paradoxes of Zeno’, The Scientific Monthly 81 (1955) 234–239.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Grünbaum, A., Modern Science and Zeno’s Paradoxes, Wesleyan University Press, Middletown, 1967 and Allen and Unwin Ltd., London, 1968 (second edition).

    Google Scholar 

  26. Grünbaum, A., Philosophical Problems of Space and Time, Alfred A. Knopf, Inc., New York, 1963.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Grünbaum, A., ‘The Philosophical Retention of Absolute Space in Einstein’s General Theory of Relativity’, Philosophical Review 66 (1957) 525–534.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  28. Grünbaum, A., ‘The Relevance of Philosophy to the History of the Special Theory of Relativity’, The Journal of Philosophy 59 (1962) 561–574.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  29. Grünbaum, A.,‘The Special Theory of Relativity as a Case Study of the Importance of the Philosophy of Science for the History of Science’, in Philosophy of Science (The Delaware Seminar, Vol. 2), (ed. by B. Baumrin), Interscience Publishers, New York, 1963, pp. 171–204.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Hobson, E. W., The Theory of Functions of a Real Variable, Vol. I, Dover Publications, Inc., New York, 1957.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Hume, D., Treatise of Human Nature, Part II, Section IV, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1941.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Landau, L. and Lifschitz, E., The Classical Theory of Fields, 2nd revised edition (transl, from the Russian by M. Hamermesh), Addison-Wesley, Reading, 1962.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Møller, C., The Theory of Relativity, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1952.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Newton, I., The Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy (intro. by Alfred del Vecchio), Citadel Press, New York, 1964.

    Google Scholar 

  35. North, J., The Measure of the Universe, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1965.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Page, L., Introduction to Theoretical Physics, D. Van Nostrand Company, New York, 1935.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Putnam, H., ‘An Examination of Grünbaum’s Philosophy of Geometry’, in Philosophy of Science (The Delaware Seminar, Vol. 2), (ed. by B. Baumrin), Interscience Publishers, New York, 1963, pp. 205–255.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Putnam, H., ‘Three-Valued Logic’, Philosophical Studies 8 (1957) 73–80.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  39. Reichenbach, H., Axiomatik der relativistischen Raum-Zeit-Lehre, F. Vieweg & Sons, Braunschweig, 1924.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Reichenbach, H., The Philosophy of Space and Time, Dover Publications, Inc., New York, 1958.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Reichenbach, H., The Rise of Scientific Philosophy, University of California Press, Berkeley, 1951.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Riemann, B., ‘On the Hypotheses Which Lie at the Foundations of Geometry’, in A Source Book in Mathematics (ed. by David E. Smith), vol. II, Dover Publications Inc., New York, 1959.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Schlick, M., ‘Are Natural Laws Conventions?’, in Readings in the Philosophy of Science (ed. by H. Feigl and M. Brodbeck), Appleton-Century-Crofts, Inc., New York, 1953, pp. 181–188.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Schlick, M., Grundzüge der Naturphilosophie, Gerold & Company, Vienna, 1948.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Synge, J., Relativity: The General Theory, North-Holland Publishing Company, Amsterdam, 1960.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Tolman, R., Relativity, Thermodynamics and Cosmology, Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1934.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Weyl, H., Space-Time-Matter, Dover Publications, Inc., New York, 1950.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Whitrow, G., The Natural Philosophy of Time, Thomas Nelson & Sons, London, 1961.

    Google Scholar 

References

  1. [37]. All my subsequent references to Putnam will be to this essay of his, and the pages from which my citations of it are drawn will be specified within ordinary parentheses in my text immediately preceding the quoted passages.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Putnam’s critique is addressed mainly to what I wrote in ‘Geometry, Chronometry, and Empiricism’, which first appeared in Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. III: Scientific Explanation, Space, and Time (ed. by H. Feigl and G. Maxwell) Minneapolis 1962, pp. 405–526. Unless otherwise specified, all references to previously published statements of mine that are criticized by Putnam are to this 1962 essay. And in order to distinguish references to it from those to Putnam’s essay, the numeral ‘1962’ will precede the appropriate page number of my essay within parentheses. Since this 1962 essay will be republished as Chapter I of my 1968 book Geometry and Chronometry in Philosophical Perspective, the additional reference ‘1968, ch. I’ may also occur in the same parentheses.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Cf. [33], p. 238.

    Google Scholar 

  4. There are also non-linear transformations between these coordinates which leave the light-velocity invariant. Cf. [40], pp. 172-175.

    Google Scholar 

  5. For the general principles relevant to the rotating rod lengths in system I, cf. [10], § 3, p. 116, and [33], p. 223.

    Google Scholar 

  6. We shall have occasion to discuss t-time light velocities on the rotating disk more fully in Section 8.2.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Thus P. Bergmann writes ([3], p. 158): “We can formulate the special theory of relativity in terms of curvilinear coordinate systems and general coordinate transformations in a four dimensional world” and ([2], p. 207) “A non-inertial frame of reference in the special theory of relativity … will include both rectilinear and curvilinear coordinate systems engaged in arbitrary motion”. As A. Janis has noted, this introduction of non-inertial frames into the STR is entirely analogous to their introduction into Newtonian mechanics: when Newton’s second law of motion is referred to non-inertial frames, it ceases to have the form F = ma, and the statement of the law then includes Coriolis and centrifugal terms among others ([36], p. 104). — The Riemann curvature-tensor is constructed solely from the components of the 4-tensor gik and from their first and second derivatives with respect to the coordinates. And this tensor enables us to speak of the gravitational field in an absolute sense. Thus J. L. Synge writes ([45], p. IX): “In Einstein’s theory, either there is a gravitational field or there is none, according as the Riemann tensor does not or does vanish. This is an absolute property; it has nothing to do with any observer’s world-line. Space-time is either flat or curved, and [one must] … separate truly gravitational effects due to curvature of space-time from those due to curvature of the observer’s world-line (in most ordinary cases the latter predominate).”

    Google Scholar 

  8. Quoted in [48], p. 170.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Theories in which the mechanical mass of, say, an electron turns out to be entirely electromagnetic (cf. [36], p. 528) are, of course, excluded here as incompatible with Putnam’s purpose to use the term ‘mass’ in intensionally alternative ways.

    Google Scholar 

  10. In the text that I omitted between the two sentences cited here, Putnam claims to correct “a major error” in my writings on Zeno’s paradoxes. I shall deal with this allegation in Section 5 below.

    Google Scholar 

  11. I disregard as irrelevant for now the broader usage of ‘GC’ in which the Chronometric part of the thesis asserts the conventionality of metrical simultaneity as well as of temporal congruence, since simultaneity will be treated in Section 8 below.

    Google Scholar 

  12. I am indebted to my mathematical colleague Albert Wilansky for clarifying comments on the presumed meaning of some of Putnam’s remarks.

    Google Scholar 

  13. (1962, p. 413, fn. 5). The two references which I give in that footnote also make it quite clear that my statements in that footnote are predicated on the countable additivity of the standard mathematical theory.

    Google Scholar 

  14. The argument which is about to be given by reference to this approximate form of the law can be readily generalized to forms of the law which allow for the temperature-dependence of the rate of thermal expansion and hence involve more than one coefficient of thermal expansion.

    Google Scholar 

  15. “This depends upon the identity of gravitational and inertial mass. The point is that in order to make the interior gravitational forces approach zero, we must make the mass of B approach zero and hence F = ma→0.”

    Google Scholar 

Editors’ Note

  • The quoting of extended passages from Hilary Putnam’s essay ‘An Examination of Grünbaum’s Philosophy of Geometry’ has been done with the kind permission of John Wiley and Sons. The passages from Albert Einstein’s essay ‘Geometry and Experience’, which first appeared in his Sidelights on Relativity (in the translation of G. B. Jeffery and W. Perrett), were quoted with the kind permission of E. P. Dutton and Co., New York, and Methuen and Co. Ltd., London.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Robert S. Cohen Marx W. Wartofsky

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1969 D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, Holland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Grünbaum, A. (1969). Reply to Hilary Putnam’s ‘An Examination of Grünbaum’s Philosophy of Geometry’. In: Cohen, R.S., Wartofsky, M.W. (eds) Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol 5. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-3381-7_1

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-3381-7_1

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-010-3383-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-010-3381-7

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics