Skip to main content

Abstract

It is often suggested that Montesquieu’s attitude to natural law was more empirical than that of the School of Natural Law in that it was more firmly based on physical realities and concrete facts and less on metaphysical ideas. This claim merits careful consideration, not only because it has a bearing on his whole conception of natural morality, but also because we find it expressed by some of his most shrewd interpreters.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Lois, vol. III, p. 287; cf. also Oudin, Le Spinozisme de Montesquieu, p. 63; Gotta, Montesquieu e la scienza délia società, pp. 356-61; Vernière, Spinoza et la pensée française, vol. II, pp. 456-7.

    Google Scholar 

  2. M., p. 252.

    Google Scholar 

  3. See Shackleton’s helpful analysis, M., p. 251.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Cf. Alengry, op. cit., pp. 393-4.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Discours sur l’origine et les fondements de l’inégalité parmi les hommes [1755], in The Political Writings of Jean-Jacques Rousseau, edited by G. E. Vaughan, Cambridge University Press, 1915, vol. I, pp. 148–52.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Cf. Ehrard, L’Idée de nature, vol. II, pp. 472–3.

    Google Scholar 

  7. In particular, he emphasized the dangers and uncertainties of the state of nature, as Hobbes had done: Dn., II, ii, 12, p. 168, and Dv., II, i, 9, pp. 253-4.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Op. cit., p. 114.

    Google Scholar 

  9. M. had first criticized this law in the L.p.: Letter GXX, N. I, iii, pp. 239-40, Pl. I, pp. 309-10.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Op. cit., Part I, III, vi, vol. I, p. 242.

    Google Scholar 

  11. 1752: 16th Proposition: see Beyer, ‘Montesquieu et la censure religieuse’, p. 127, n. 1.

    Google Scholar 

  12. W. Stark, Montesquieu, Pioneer of the Sociology of Knowledge, Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1960, p. 196.

    Google Scholar 

  13. In this passage, Pufendorf was talking mainly of crimes where the offender has already offered restitution for the damage done, but he seems to go on to apply the principle to all crimes, as he does in Dn., VIII, iii, 4, vol. II, p. 376.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Brethe de la Gressaye, Lois, vol. III, p. 438, n. 36, to p. 278.

    Google Scholar 

  15. See below, Ch. 6, II

    Google Scholar 

  16. Lois, vol. III, p. 287.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Cf. P. Vernière, ‘L’Idée d’humanité au XVIIIe siècle’, Studium Generale, 1962, pp. 171. 9.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Op. cit., Traité des lois, i, I, vol. I, p. i.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Ibid., Le Droit public, Preface, vol. II, p. [viii].

    Google Scholar 

  20. Dn., VI, i, 2-5, vol. II, pp. 150-3; cf. Gravina, Origines iuris civilis, II, iv, p. 238.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Op. cit., Traité des lois, iii, 1-2, vol. I, p. iv.

    Google Scholar 

  22. In the Latin: “non per modicum tempus, sed diu: vel etiam per totam vitam” (S. Thomœ Aquinatis Summa totius theologiœ, Antwerp, Ex officina Christophori Plantini, 1585, Secunda secundæ, p. 303).

    Google Scholar 

  23. Though Pufendorf did mention that marriage had been instituted by God, it was only in passing (Dn., VI, i, 2, vol.II p. 150).

    Google Scholar 

  24. Le Spinozisme de Montesquieu, pp. 36–7.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Montesquieu e la scienza della sociétà, p. 192.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Dg., II, v, 2-6, vol. I, pp. 279-81; Pufendorf, Dn., VI, ii, 7-12, vol. II, pp. 192-9; T.T., II, vi, 58-65, pp. 324-9.

    Google Scholar 

  27. The same reasoning is found in S.t., II, ii, Q. 154, A. 9, vol. XIII, pp. 153-4.

    Google Scholar 

  28. We are here considering only the Lois; in P. 205 (Bkn. 1928), N. II, pp. 74-7, Pl. I, pp. 1463-5, M. did not consider incest to be unnatural, but he did refer to the principle of respect.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Montesquieu e la scienza della società, p. 368.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Cf. Crocker, Nature and Culture, pp. 360–1.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Observations sur le livre de l’Esprit des lois, p. 214.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Les Confessions, II, in Œuvres complètes, edited by B. Gagnebin and M. Raymond, Bibliothèque de la Pléiade, vol. I, 1962, p. 69.

    Google Scholar 

  33. M., p. 253.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Ibid., pp. 255-6.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Ibid., p. 256.

    Google Scholar 

  36. De finibus bonorum et malorum, III, v–vii; in the Loeb edition, pp. 232-45; St. Paul, Epistle to the Romans, VII, 22-3.

    Google Scholar 

  37. In S.t., II, i, Q.94, A. 2, vol. VIII, p. 44, he accepts that one kind of natural law is common to man and the animals, but he gives priority to the natural law of reason, found in man alone (cf. also S.t., II, i, Q.I, A. 1, vol. VI, p. 2).

    Google Scholar 

  38. Hobbes tried to prove that the equality of primitive man, or rather, the ability of even the weakest to kill the strongest, made the state of nature into a state of war (P.R., i, 3, pp. 6-7).

    Google Scholar 

  39. Montesquieu, I’Esprit des lois, p. 23.

    Google Scholar 

  40. M., p. 258, n. 1.

    Google Scholar 

  41. M., p. 259.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Discours de la méthode, V, pp. 45–6; Traité de l’homme, p. 120; cf. F. Bouillier, Histoire de la philosophie cartésienne, Delagrave, 1868, vol. I, pp. 150 and 163-6.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Cf. Bouillier, op. cit., vol. I, pp. 148-9.

    Google Scholar 

  44. At least, he claimed to be following the a priori method, in his attempt to deduce natural law from the principle of benevolence (Traitéphilosophique des lois naturelles, Disc, prél., iv, pp. 6-7 and i, 7, pp. 46-7).

    Google Scholar 

  45. Diderot and Descartes, A Study of Scientific Naturalism in the Enlightenment, Princeton University Press, 1953: see especially pp. 203–88.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Some recent exponents of M.’s determinism are: Henry Vyverberg, Historical Pessimism in the French Enlightenment, Harvard University Press, 1958, pp. 158–9; L. G. Crocker, An Age of Crisis, Man and World in Eighteenth-Century French Thought, The Johns Hopkins Press, 1959, p. 75. Convincing denials of this interpretation have been made by: C. E. Vaughan, Studies in the History of Political Philosophy Before and After Rousseau, Manchester University Press, 1925, vol. I, p. 271; G. Davy,’ sur la méthode de Montesquieu’, Revue de métaphysique et de morale, 1939, PP-575-82; Sir Isaiah Berlin, ‘Montesquieu’, pp. 286-7; Roger Mercier, ‘La Notion de loi morale chez Montesquieu’, Proceedings of the Sixth Triennial Congress of the International Federation for Modern Languages and Literatures, Oxford, Blackwell, 1955, pp. 191-2; Aron, op. cit., p. 36.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Crocker, Nature and Culture, pp. 28–9, seems to overlook this fact.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1970 Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, Netherlands

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Waddicor, M.H. (1970). Montesquieu and Empiricism in Natural Law. In: Montesquieu and the Philosophy of Natural Law. Archives Internationales D’Histoire des Idées / International Archives of the History of Ideas, vol 37. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-3238-4_3

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-3238-4_3

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-010-3240-7

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-010-3238-4

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics