Skip to main content

Spiritual Conversion and the Transfiguration of Values

  • Chapter
The Philosophy of Georges Bastide
  • 30 Accesses

Abstract

We have so far proceeded from our original affirmation, through the problematic which it posed (the problem of authentic existence), to an analysis of the human condition — all in an effort to clarify man’s situation in the world and discover a method for the authentic employment of an axiological metaphysics. An analysis of the human condition revealed the structure of inauthenticity as genetically linked to the maturation of consciousness as it receives an essentially new orientation. That is, a consideration of the “conscience malheureuse” revealed that inauthenticity and the conscious awareness of this condition, when resolutely faced by a generous will, effected a dramatic and wholly new attitude of consciousness. It is this change that is signified by the term “spiritual conversion” and we must now proceed to point out the full ramifications of this movement in Bastide’s philosophy.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Cf. G. Bastide, Traité, p. 133 of T.I.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Ibid., p. 133; cf. also G. Bastide, De la condition humaine, p. 284.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Cf. G. Bastide, Traité, p. 140.

    Google Scholar 

  4. G. Bastide, Méditations, p. 129.

    Google Scholar 

  5. G. Bastide, Les grands thèmes, p. 91.

    Google Scholar 

  6. The primitive function of judgment does not distinguish between value judgments and existential judgments. For in the early stages of consciousness’ development “the object has no reality except by its value and no value except with reference to a subject.” The judgment is, in this context, a confrontation of subject-object, such that the subject has no reality expect by its tension and no consciousness of its tension except by reference to the object. Cf. G. Bastide, De la condition humaine, p. 79.

    Google Scholar 

  7. The first part of Bastide’s De la condition humaine is devoted to a psychological consideration of the development of consciousness as it moves towards reflection and spiritual conversion. Bastide’s purpose is to discover the essential and fundamental needs of all conscious life, since these already point to the metaphysical order in some way. Id. p. 34. All along the way of the reflexive method the objective disciplines (which consider man “outside himself”) are necessary, since they afford reflection the elements of a “constant confrontation” in the “constant check of verification.” There is a “felicitous synchronism,” says Bastide, “between the objective critiques of the primtive, infant and pathological mentalities (Lévy-Bruhl, Jean Piaget, Pierre Janet) and the reflexive analyses of the idealists, together with the historical perspectives of Brunschvicg himself. Cf. G. Bastide, De la Condition humaine, pp. 6–7.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Cf. Note §9, part. II, chapter II.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Cf. G. Bastide, De la condition humaine, pp. 133–134.

    Google Scholar 

  10. De la condition humaine, G. Bastide, p. 284.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Cf. G. Bastide De la condition humaine, p. 284.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Cf. G. Bastide, Traité, p. 141.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Cf. G. Bastide, Traité, p. 141.

    Google Scholar 

  14. While the terminology of idealism is at times strange to a realist point of view, it is necessary to see it always in the light of its original project of placing the spontaneity of thought in a non-objectivist context, in a philosophy of action. The incorporation of the life elan of Bergson into the idealist context is not without foundation. Cf. A. Dondeyne, “Idealisme of realisme?” Tijdschrift voor Philosophie, 1941 (November), p. 614.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Cf. A. Cresson, Maine de Biran, Paris, 1950, pp. 123 and 128.

    Google Scholar 

  16. It is a question here of making precise the notion of spirit. Bastide accepts Kant’s critique against ontological substantialism. But Bastide believes that Kant missed the full creative nature of spirit by reason of the formalism of his method, which passed from the given to the metaphysical conditions in the direction of an absolute purity. Anxious to complete his revolution Kant ended up by giving a structure to “human consciousness in general” in the a priori forms. As such, says Bastide, transcendental idealism, in so far as it attempts to translate this structural conception of spirit, was an unstable equilibrium between subjectivism and absolute idealism. The problem is to reconcile the concrete, individual and dynamic aspects of personal subject with the universal and objective character of human existence. Eventually Bastide finds the orientation of his solution in the practical philosophy of Kant. In the postulates of practical reason and in a practical faith the spirit is attained on a new level, especially if the tendency to formalism is avoided by an approach to spirit in its “hand to hand” engagement with the problem of its existence not only as immanence but as transcendence as well, i.e. the notion of spirit as tension in an axiological metaphysics of action. Cf. G. Bastide, De la condition humaine, pp. 293–303.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Cf. G. Bastide, De la condition humaine, p. 302.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Ibid., p. 313.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Ibid., p. 317.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Cf. G. Bastide, De la condition humaine, p. 284.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Cf. Note § 13 of this chapter.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Bastide gives a very enlightening exposition, from a psychological point of view, of the various forms of psychological alienation in De la condition humaine, pp. 177–194.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Cf. G. Bastide, De la condition humaine, p. 319.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Cf. G. Bastide, De la condition humaine, p. 366.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Ibid., p. 321.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Cf. G. Bastide, De la condition humaine, p. 319.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Ibid., p. 320.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Cf. G. Bastide, “La conversion spirituelle,” op. cit., p. 19.06-4.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Cf. G. Bastide, De la condition humaine, p. 321.

    Google Scholar 

  32. De la condition humaine, p. 322.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Cf. G. Bastide, “Le malin génie,” op. cit., p. 240.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Cf. G. Bastide, “Le malin génie,” op. cit., p. 240.

    Google Scholar 

  35. G. Bastide, Traité, p. 133.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Cf. G. Bastide, “De la condition temporelle de l’homme,” Les études philosophiques, 1962 (17), p. 80.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Cf. G. Bastide, “The Metaphysical Dimensions of Man,” op. cit., p. 351.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Id.

    Google Scholar 

  39. “Three spheres of reality here detach themselves from one another: the sphere of ‘corps,’ that of ‘esprits’ and that of ‘charité.’ Between them lies a ‘différence de genre’;... each sphere has its own kind of value... Associated with each is a particular cognitive prerequisite and a particular ‘vue,’ a view corresponding to the specific object.” R. Guardina, “Man and his situation in the world,” in Pascal for our Time, translated by B. Thompson, Herder (New York), 1966, p. 72.

    Google Scholar 

  40. G. Bastide, “The Metaphysical Dimensions...” op. cit., p. 354.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Cf. G. Bastide, “La nature, la conscience,” op. cit., p. 27.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Cf. G. Bastide, De la condition humaine, p. 376.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Cf. G. Bastide, Traité, p. 166.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Cf. G. Bastide, “La condition spirituelle,” op. cit., p. 19.06-5.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Cf. G. Bastide, La conversion spirituelle, p. 66.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Cf. G. Bastide, Traité, p. 357.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Id., p. 358.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Cf. G. Bastide, Méditations, pp. 104–106.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Cf. G. Bastide, “The Metaphysical Dimensions of Man,” op. cit., p. 355.

    Google Scholar 

  50. G. Bastide, “La Conversion spirituelle,” op. cit., p. 19.06-6.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Cf. G. Bastide, La conversion spirituelle, p. 46.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Ibid., p. 6.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Ibid., pp. 54–55.

    Google Scholar 

  54. Cf. G. Bastide, Traité, p. 134.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Ibid., p. 135; see also La conversion spirituelle, p. 55.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Cf. G. Bastide, La conversion spirituelle, op. cit., p. 19.06-6.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Ibid., p. 19.06-7.

    Google Scholar 

  58. G. Bastide, Traité, p. 135.

    Google Scholar 

  59. Ibid., p. 136. See as well pp. 190–191 and La conversion spirituelle, pp. 650–66.

    Google Scholar 

  60. Cf. G. Bastide, Traité, p. 136; also De la condition humaine, pp. 329–331.

    Google Scholar 

  61. G. Bastide, “De la situation de l’homme,” op. cit., p. 245.

    Google Scholar 

  62. G. Bastide, “The Metaphysical Dimensions of Man,” op. cit., p. 353.

    Google Scholar 

  63. G. Bastide, Traité, p. 127.

    Google Scholar 

  64. G. Bastide, “The Metaphysical Dimensions,” p. 360. We are in the practical order of the postulates of the practical reason.

    Google Scholar 

  65. Id., p. 365.

    Google Scholar 

  66. Cf. La conversion spirituelle, p. 66.

    Google Scholar 

  67. Ibid., p. 69.

    Google Scholar 

  68. Cf. G. Bastide, Méditations, p. 104.

    Google Scholar 

  69. Cf. G. Bastide, Méditations, p. 106.

    Google Scholar 

  70. Id., p. 108.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1971 Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, Netherlands

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Koenig, T. (1971). Spiritual Conversion and the Transfiguration of Values. In: The Philosophy of Georges Bastide. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-3045-8_6

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-3045-8_6

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-010-3047-2

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-010-3045-8

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics