Skip to main content

The Development of Mead’s Thought

  • Chapter
The Social Dynamics of George H. Mead
  • 129 Accesses

Abstract

It is possible to approach the philosophy, sociology, and social psychology of George H. Mead in at least two major ways, depending on whether his thought is considered to be a systematic unity in which all central themes mesh internally and consistently, or whether Mead’s work is comprehended as a series of significant efforts to explore the nature of social reality from separate though genetically related perspectives which reveal serious internal deviations and tensions. Choice of approach is not an arbitrary matter: both modes of investigating Mead’s ideas necessarily have their limitations; but it is our conviction that the profound and original themes Mead explored in his intellectual life-time can best be grasped by choosing to follow the development in his thought that led him, in our view, from “social behaviorism” to a position which transcends behaviorism of any sort. The validity and value of our selected mode of procedure can, of course, be demonstrated only through an extended presentation. The exposition of the decisive and variant aspects of Mead’s thought through a developmental analysis is the necessary preparation for the critical evaluation of his thought.

“Man is rooted in society and his instincts are addressed to it.” —George Santayana

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

“Mind, Self, and Society”-The First Phase

  1. MSS, p. 1.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  3. lbid.

    Google Scholar 

  4. MSS, p. 132.

    Google Scholar 

  5. MSS, p. 133.

    Google Scholar 

  6. lbid.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  9. MSS, footnote pp. 13–14.

    Google Scholar 

  10. MSS, p. 14; see also Ibid., pp. 42-43, 63.

    Google Scholar 

  11. MSS, p. 46.

    Google Scholar 

  12. MSS, p. 47.

    Google Scholar 

  13. MSS, footnote p. 81.

    Google Scholar 

  14. MSS, p. 67.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  16. MSS, p. 14.

    Google Scholar 

  17. MSS, p. 73; Cf. George H. Mead, What Social Objects Must Psychology Presupposer Journal of Phibsophy, Vol. VII, 1910, p. 178ff.

    Google Scholar 

  18. MSS, p. 97.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  20. MSS, p. 77.

    Google Scholar 

  21. MSS, p. 78.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  23. MSS, p. 80.

    Google Scholar 

  24. MSS, p. 81.

    Google Scholar 

  25. MSS, p. 10.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  28. MSS, p. 30.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  30. MSS, p. 332.

    Google Scholar 

  31. MSS, p. 329.

    Google Scholar 

  32. MSS, p. 136.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  34. MSS, p. 137 and footnote on p. 137.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Although Mead develops extended analyses of problems involved in “role-taking,” he does not offer much toward the understanding of “role-taking” as such; the term remains undefined, though it is clear that to take the role of another is to put oneself in the place of another individual: see MSS, footnote, p. 141.

    Google Scholar 

  36. MSS, p. 150.

    Google Scholar 

  37. MSS, p. 151.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  39. MSS, p. 152.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  41. MSS, p. 154.

    Google Scholar 

  42. MSS, p. 155; Cf. Mead’s “A Behavioristic Account of the Significant Symbol,” Journal of Philosophy, Vol. XIX, 1922, pp. 161-62; also his “The Mechanism of Social Consciousness,” Ibid., Vol. IX, 1912, p. 402 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  43. MSS, footnote p. 155.

    Google Scholar 

  44. MSS, p. 156.

    Google Scholar 

  45. MSS, p. 173.

    Google Scholar 

  46. MSS, p. 197; Cf. “The Mechanism of Social Consciousness,” op. cit., p. 405 ff.; also Mead’s “The Social Self,” Journal of Philosophy, Vol. X, 1913, p. 375.

    Google Scholar 

  47. MSS, p. 178.

    Google Scholar 

  48. MSS, p. 174.

    Google Scholar 

  49. MSS, p. 178.

    Google Scholar 

  50. MSS, p. 199.

    Google Scholar 

  51. MSS, p. 182.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Cf. Jean-Paul Sartre, L’Etre et le néant, Paris: Gallimard, 1943, pp. 561–638; also Sartre’s Anti-Semite and Jew (tr. by George J. Becker) New York: Schocken Books, 1948, pp. 59-60; see Maurice Natanson, A Critique of Jean-Paul Sartre’s Ontology, University of Nebraska Studies, Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press, 1951, p. 49 ff., p. 57 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  53. W. I. Thomas and Dorothy Swaine Thomas, The Chad in America, N.Y.: Alfred A. Knopf, 1938, p. 572: “If men define situations as real, they are real in their consequences”; Cf. W. I. Thomas, The Unadjusted Girl, Boston: Little, Brown and Co., 1923, pp. 41-44 and Social Behavior and Personality: Contributions of W. I. Thomas to Theory and Social Research,(edited by Edmund H. Volkart), N.Y.: Social Science Research Council, 1951, p. 81.

    Google Scholar 

  54. This concept is taken from Alfred Schütz. See his “Common-Sense and Scientific Interpretation of Human Action,” Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, Vol. XIV, No. 1, Sept., 1953, p. 6 and also “Choosing Among Projects of Action,” Ibid., Vol. XII, No. 2, Dec. 1951, pp. 168-69.

    Google Scholar 

  55. MSS, p. 201.

    Google Scholar 

  56. “The Genesis of the Self and Social Control,” International Journal of Ethics, Vol. XXXV, 1924–25, pp. 263–64 (quoted in MSS, footnote, p. 7).

    Google Scholar 

  57. MSS, p. 18.

    Google Scholar 

“The Philosophy of the Act”-The Second Phase

  1. MSS, p. 7

    Google Scholar 

  2. PA, p. 364.

    Google Scholar 

  3. PA, p. 65.

    Google Scholar 

  4. PA, p. 147.

    Google Scholar 

  5. PA, p. 3.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  8. PA, pp. 4–5.

    Google Scholar 

  9. PA, p. 5.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  11. PA, p. 7.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  14. PA, p. 6.

    Google Scholar 

  15. PA, p. 7.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  17. PA, p. 8.

    Google Scholar 

  18. PA, p. 3.

    Google Scholar 

  19. PA, p. 8.

    Google Scholar 

  20. PA, p. 9.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  24. PA, pp. 9–10.

    Google Scholar 

  25. PA, p. 10.

    Google Scholar 

  26. We have taken the concept and terminology of “world taken for granted” from Alfred Schütz; see his “Choosing Among Projects of Action,” op. cit., p. 166 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  27. PA, p. 11.

    Google Scholar 

  28. PA, p. 12.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  30. PA, pp. 12–13.

    Google Scholar 

  31. PA, p. 13.

    Google Scholar 

  32. PA, p. 14.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  35. PA, p. 16.

    Google Scholar 

  36. PA, p. 18.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  38. PA, p. 20.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  41. PA, p. 227.

    Google Scholar 

  42. PA, p. 121; cf. “The Mechanism of Social Consciousness,” op. cit., p. 401.

    Google Scholar 

  43. PA, p. 128.

    Google Scholar 

  44. PA, p. 122.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  46. PA, p. 151.

    Google Scholar 

  47. PA, p. 19.

    Google Scholar 

  48. PA, p. 22.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  50. PA, p. 197.

    Google Scholar 

  51. PA, p. 196.

    Google Scholar 

  52. PA, p. 141.

    Google Scholar 

  53. PA, p. 142.

    Google Scholar 

  54. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  55. PA, p. 136.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  57. PA, p. 24.

    Google Scholar 

  58. PA, p. 25.

    Google Scholar 

  59. PA, p. 23; see also Ibid., pp. 451-52.

    Google Scholar 

  60. PA, pp. 454–55.

    Google Scholar 

  61. MSS, p. 185.

    Google Scholar 

  62. MSS, p. 184.

    Google Scholar 

  63. PA, p. 30.

    Google Scholar 

  64. PA, p. 29.

    Google Scholar 

  65. PA, p. 30.

    Google Scholar 

  66. PA, p. 45.

    Google Scholar 

  67. PA, p. 104.

    Google Scholar 

  68. PA, p. 103.

    Google Scholar 

  69. PA, p. 108.

    Google Scholar 

  70. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  71. PA, p. 109.

    Google Scholar 

  72. PA, p. 110.

    Google Scholar 

  73. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  74. PA, p. 428.

    Google Scholar 

  75. PA, p. 429.

    Google Scholar 

  76. PA, p. 431.

    Google Scholar 

  77. PA, p. 212.

    Google Scholar 

  78. PA, p. 213.

    Google Scholar 

  79. PA, p. 152.

    Google Scholar 

  80. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  81. PA, pp. 160–64.

    Google Scholar 

  82. PA, pp. 159–60.

    Google Scholar 

  83. PA, pp. 160–61.

    Google Scholar 

  84. PA, p. 161.

    Google Scholar 

  85. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  86. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  87. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  88. PA, p. 162.

    Google Scholar 

  89. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  90. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  91. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  92. PA, p. 163.

    Google Scholar 

  93. PA, p. 343.

    Google Scholar 

  94. PA, pp. 343–44.

    Google Scholar 

  95. PA, p. 344.

    Google Scholar 

  96. PA, p. 345.

    Google Scholar 

  97. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  98. PA, p. 347.

    Google Scholar 

  99. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  100. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  101. PA, p. 348.

    Google Scholar 

  102. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  103. PA, p. 635.

    Google Scholar 

  104. PA, p. 178.

    Google Scholar 

  105. PA, p. 178.

    Google Scholar 

  106. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  107. PA, p. 179.

    Google Scholar 

  108. The term “perspectives” in this context refers to Whitehead’s terminology rather than to “standpoints” in role-taldng discussed previously in regard to Mind, Self, and Society.

    Google Scholar 

  109. PA, p. 199.

    Google Scholar 

  110. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  111. PA, p. 112.

    Google Scholar 

  112. PA, pp. 99–100.

    Google Scholar 

  113. PA, p. 114.

    Google Scholar 

  114. PA, p. 115.

    Google Scholar 

  115. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  116. PA, p. 182.

    Google Scholar 

  117. PA, pp. 118–19.

    Google Scholar 

  118. PA, p. 119.

    Google Scholar 

  119. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  120. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  121. PA, p. 115.

    Google Scholar 

  122. PA, p. 243.

    Google Scholar 

  123. PA, p. 115.

    Google Scholar 

  124. PA, p. 284.

    Google Scholar 

  125. PA, pp. 284–88.

    Google Scholar 

“The Philosophy of the Present”-The Third Phase

  1. PP, p. 1.

    Google Scholar 

  2. PP, p. 1; Cf. PA, pp. 355-56 and PP, pp. 19-20.

    Google Scholar 

  3. PP, p. 1.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  5. “The Nature of the Past,” in Essays in Honor of John Detvey, New York: Henry Holt & Co., 1929, p. 238.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Ibid.; Cf. MT, pp. 292-325, 496 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  7. PP, p. 21.

    Google Scholar 

  8. PP, p. 2.

    Google Scholar 

  9. The Nature of the Past, op. cit., p. 240; Cf. Harold N. Lee, “The Hypothetical Nature of Historical Knowledge,” Journal of Philosophy, Vol. LI, No. 7, April 1, 1954, pp. 213–220; Bruce Waters, “The Past and the Historical Past,” Ibid., Vol. LII, No. 10, May 12, 1955, pp. 253-269; Michael Oakeshott, Experience and Us Modes, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1933.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  10. PP, p. 12.

    Google Scholar 

  11. PP, p. 26.

    Google Scholar 

  12. PP, p. 33.

    Google Scholar 

  13. PP, pp. 17–18.

    Google Scholar 

  14. The Nature of the Past, op. cit., p. 238.

    Google Scholar 

  15. PP, p. 30.

    Google Scholar 

  16. PP, p. 31.

    Google Scholar 

  17. PP, p. 1: “The present of course implies a past and a future, and to these both we deny existence.”

    Google Scholar 

  18. “The Philosophies of Royce, James, and Dewey in their American Setting,” in John Dewey: The Man and his Philosophy, Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1930, p. 79.

    Google Scholar 

  19. PA, p. 216.

    Google Scholar 

  20. PA, p. 353.

    Google Scholar 

  21. PA, p. 413.

    Google Scholar 

  22. PP, p. 14.

    Google Scholar 

  23. PP, p. 1.

    Google Scholar 

  24. PP, p. 11.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  26. PA, pp. 413–14; Cf. PA, pp. 87-88.

    Google Scholar 

  27. PA, p. 21.

    Google Scholar 

  28. The concept of “relevance” as a part of the “biographical situation” of the individual is taken from Alfred Schütz; see his Der sinnhafte Aufbau der sozialen Welt, Vienna: Julius Springer, 1932, pp. 284–85 and also “Common-Sense and Scientific Interpretation of Human Action,” op. cit., pp. 5-6 and passim.

    Google Scholar 

  29. PP, pp. 24–25.

    Google Scholar 

  30. PP, p. 25.

    Google Scholar 

  31. PP, p. 11.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Ibid.

    Google Scholar 

  34. PP, pp. 11–12.

    Google Scholar 

  35. PP, p. 15.

    Google Scholar 

  36. PP, p. 64.

    Google Scholar 

  37. PP, p. 69.

    Google Scholar 

  38. PP, p. 67.

    Google Scholar 

  39. PP, p. 162.

    Google Scholar 

  40. PP, p. 163; Cf. William Hammerschmidt, Whttehead’s Theory of Time, New York: Kings Crown Press, 1947.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1973 Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, Netherlands

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Natanson, M. (1973). The Development of Mead’s Thought. In: The Social Dynamics of George H. Mead. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-2408-2_2

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-2408-2_2

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-247-1489-6

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-010-2408-2

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics