Skip to main content

The Confusion between Science and Technology in the Standard Philosophies of Science

  • Chapter
Contributions to a Philosophy of Technology

Part of the book series: Theory and Decision Library ((TDLU,volume 5))

Abstract

The distinction between pure and applied science seems too trivial to draw, since applied science, as the name implies, aims at practical ends, whereas pure science does not. There is an overlap, to be sure, which is known as fundamental research and which is pure science in the short run but applied in the long run; that is to say, fundamental research is the search for certain laws of nature with an eye to using these laws. Still, this overlap shows that though the distinction is not exclusive it is clear enough. The distinction between applied science and technology is a different matter altogether. All philosophers of science equate them, whereas it is clear that technology includes, at the very least, applied science, invention, implementation of the results of both applied science and invention, and the maintenance of the existing apparatus, especially in the face of unexpected changes, disasters, and so forth. The distinction between applied science and invention, to my knowledge, was made by only one writer, the most important writer on technology, perhaps; I am referring to H. S. Hatfield and his The Inventor and His World. Hatfield does not draw the distinction explicitly, but he uses it clearly and systematically enough. Applied science, according to his view, is an exercise in deduction, whereas invention is finding a needle in a haystack.

First published in Technology and Culture 7 (1966), 348–366.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  • K. R. Popper, ‘Three Views Concerning Human Knowledge’, Contemporary British Philosophy (ed. by H. D. Lewis), London, 1956, pp. 355–88; and Conjectures and Refutations, London and New York, 1962, pp. 97–119. See also my ‘Duhem versus Galileo’, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science VIII (1957), 237–48.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthew Josephson, Edison (paperbound ed.), New York, 1959, pp. ix-xi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pierre Simon, Marquis de Laplace, ‘Application of the Calculus of Probabilities to Moral Philosophy’, A Philosophical Essay on Probabilities ( paperbound ed.), New York, 1951, Chap. X.

    Google Scholar 

  • Josephson, Edison, p. 198.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rudolf Carnap, Logical Foundations of Probability (2d ed.), Chicago, 1962, p. 193.

    Google Scholar 

  • ‘A General Estimation Function’, in Rudolf Carnap, Logical Foundations of Probability (2d ed.), Chicago, 1962, p. 193, Sec. 99 ff. See also his ‘On Inductive Logic’, Philosophy of Science XII (1945), Sec. 10 (reprinted in Probability Confirmation, and Simplicity (ed. by M. H. Foster and M. L. Martin), New York, 1966). Cf. Popper, ‘On Carnap’s Version of Laplace’s Rule of Succession’, Mind LXXI CI962) 69–73; and my ‘Analogies as Generalizations’, Philosophy of Science XXXI (1964), 351–56.

    Google Scholar 

  • J. Wolfowitz, ‘Abraham Wald’, Annals of Mathematical Statistics XXXIII (1952), 9: “… was put on the restricted category and made available only to authorized recipients. Wald chafed greatly under this restriction.” Cf. Statistical Research Group, Columbia University, Selected Techniques of Statistical Analysis for Social and Industrial Research and Production Management, New York, 1947, pp. viii-ix.

    Google Scholar 

  • William Whewell, The Philosophy of the Inductive Sciences, London, 1840, Vol. II, Part 2, Book XI, Chap, i, Sees. 6, 10; Chap, v, Sees. 7, 8 (about testing), 10 (about techniques of testing: predictions), 11 (about the stringency of the test: new prediction), 12, 13 (correlating simplicity and testability, so to speak); Chap, vi, Sec. 12(non-adhocness). See also his History of the Inductive Sciences (3d ed.), London, 1843, Vol. I, Book VII, ‘The Discovery of Neptune’: “Thus to predict unknown facts found afterwards to be true, is, as I have said, a confirmation of a theory which in impressiveness and value goes beyond any known explanation of known facts.” And such confirmation, he says, took place only a few times in the whole history of man.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, The Logic of Scientific Discovery, New York, 1959, Chap, x and New Appendix, IX.

    Google Scholar 

  • Josephson, Edison, p. 198.

    Google Scholar 

  • Michael Polanyi, Pure and Applied Science and Their Appropriate Forms of Organization, Society for Freedom in Science, Occasional Pamphlet No. 14, Oxford, December 1953, p. 2. See also p. 9.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pierre Duhem, The Aim and Structure of Physical Theory (paperbound ed.), Princeton, N. J., 1962, Part 1, Chap, ii; Part 2, Chap, iii; and Appendix ‘The Value of Physical Theory’.

    Google Scholar 

  • E. Mach, ‘The Economical Nature of Physical Research’, Popular Scientific Lectures, La Salle, Ill., 1907, Chap, xiii; his The Science of Mechanics (paperbound ed.), La Salle, Ill., 1960, Chap, iv, Sec. 4.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, ‘Three Views’ (see n. 2), Sec. 5: ‘Criticism of the Instrumentalist View’.

    Google Scholar 

  • Erik H. Erikson, ‘Autonomy vs. Shame and Doubt’, Childhood and Society (2d ed.), New York, 1963, Chap, vii, Sec. 2, p. 253

    Google Scholar 

  • Allen Wheelis, The Quest for Identity, New York, 1958, Chap, vi, esp. pp. 183, 199, 201, 250.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, Conjectures, Chap, x, Sec. 23, and note on p. 248.

    Google Scholar 

  • J. M. Keynes, Treatise on Probability, Cambridge, 1921, Chap, xxiii, esp. p. 271.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, Conjectures, p. 217: “I assert that we know what a good scientific theory should be like, and - even before it has been tested - what kind of theory would be better still, provided it passes certain crucial tests.” And on p. 242, “The second requirement ensures that….”

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, ‘The Aim of Science’, Ratio I (1957), 24–35. See also my ‘Between Micro and Macro’, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science XIV (1963).

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, ‘Naturgesetze und Wirklichkeit’, in Gesetz und Wirklichkeit (ed. by S. Moser), Innsbruck, 1949, pp. 43–60, esp. pp. 53 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  • H. Stafford Hatfield, The Inventor and His World, 1933; Pelican ed., 1948, pp. 111, 133, 134, 151, et passim.

    Google Scholar 

  • Josephson, Edison, Chap, x, esp. p. 194. Cf. Usher, A History of Mechanical Invention, pp. 72–77 and 401–6.

    Google Scholar 

  • Helmut Gernsheim, in collaboration with Alison Gernsheim, The History of Photography from the Earliest Use of the Camera Obscura in the Eleventh Century up to 1914, Oxford, 1955.

    Google Scholar 

  • Helmut Gernsheim, in collaboration with Alison Gernsheim, The History of Photography from the Earliest Use of the Camera Obscura in the Eleventh Century up to 1914, Oxford, 1955, p. 81.

    Google Scholar 

  • Helmut and Alison Gernsheim, L. J. M. Daguerre: A History of the Diorama and the Daguerreotype, London, 1955; American ed., published under title L.M.J. Daguerre, the World’s First Photographer, Cleveland, 1956.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruth Mitchell, My Brother Bill: The Life of General ‘Billy’ Mitchell, with an Introduction by Gerald W. Johnson, New York, 1953, pp. 12–13: “There was a moment when he seemed to be entirely right. But events in Korea, where our separate airforce has accomplished nothing… prove…. But even if he had been wholly wrong….”

    Google Scholar 

  • Noam Chomsky, ‘Explanatory Models in Linguistics’, in Logic, Methodology, and Philosophy of Science (ed. by E. Nagel, P. Suppes and A. Tarski), Proceedings of the 1960 International Congress, Stanford, Calif., 1962, pp. 528–50.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1966 The University of Chicago Press

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Agassi, J. (1966). The Confusion between Science and Technology in the Standard Philosophies of Science. In: Rapp, F. (eds) Contributions to a Philosophy of Technology. Theory and Decision Library, vol 5. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-2182-1_3

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-2182-1_3

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-010-2184-5

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-010-2182-1

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics