Skip to main content
  • 83 Accesses

Abstract

The word liberal defies precise definition since its usage includes a variety of meanings in a number of different contexts. The word liberal has at least three connotations: (1) personal, (2) political and (3) economic. The difficulty of precisely defining liberalism is further compounded by the fact that it has somewhat different meanings in different historical periods. Nor is there agreement among scholars as to its historical origins since its convictions derive both from ancient and modern sources. Thus one scholar describes liberalism as “the modern embodiment of all the characteristic traditions of Western politics,” 1 while another would define it more narrowly as the embodiment of the political aspirations of a bourgeois middle-class society, as the political counterpart of capitalism.2

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Frederick Watkins, The Political Tradition of the West (Cambridge, Mass., 1948), p. ix.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Harold J. Laski, The Rise of European Liberalism (London, 1936).

    Google Scholar 

  3. Liberalism: Its Theory and Practice (Austin, Texas, 1958), p. 23.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Liberalism and Industry (London, 1920), p. 15.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Introduction to Political Philosophy (New York, 1952), p. 207.

    Google Scholar 

  6. “The individual human being, with his interests, his enterprise, his desire for happiness and advancement, above all with his reason, which seemed the condition for a successful use of all his other faculties, appeared to be the foundation on which a stable society must be built.... Not man as a priest or soldier, as the member of a guild or an estate, but man as a bare human being, a ‘masterless man,’ appeared to be the solid fact.” George H. Sabine, A History of Political Theory, (2nd ed.; New York, 1950), p. 432.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Was istAufklärung? 1784, Werke, ed. by E. Cassirer (Berlin, 1922), Vol. 4, p. 169.

    Google Scholar 

  8. “Enlightenment,” in the Encyclopedia of the Social Sciences (New York, 1937), Vol. 5, p. 547.

    Google Scholar 

  9. The Philosophical Works of Descartes, transi, by Haldane and Ross (Cambridge, 1931), Part 6.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Cf. Louis Hartz, The Liberal Tradition in America (New York, 1955).

    Google Scholar 

  11. Cf. Herbert Spencer, “Progress: Its Law and Cause,” Illustrations of Universal Progress (New York, 1864).

    Google Scholar 

  12. Wealth of Nations, Book I, Chap. IV.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Ibid., Book IV, Chap. II.

    Google Scholar 

  14. “The Challenge of Facts,” in Essays of William Graham Sumner, ed. by A. G. Keller and M. R. David (New Haven, 1934), Vol. II, pp. 87ff.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Adventures of Ideas (New York, 1933), p. 39.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Gorgias, 492.

    Google Scholar 

  17. I have described this process in some detail in The Decline of Liberalism as an Ideology (Berkeley, 1943). Reprinted by Howard Fertig (New York, 1971).

    Google Scholar 

  18. Cf. C. H. Mcllwain, Constitutionalism: Ancient and Modern (Ithaca, N.Y., 1940).

    Google Scholar 

  19. The New Science of Politics (Chicago, 1952), p. 189.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Theology of Society (London, 1947), pp. 64–66.

    Google Scholar 

  21. The New Science of Politics, p. 131.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Cf. Science, Politics and Gnosticism (Chicago, 1968).

    Google Scholar 

  23. See Eric Voegelin, “On Hegel: A Study in Sorcery,” Studium Generale, Vol. 24 (1971), pp. 335–368.

    Google Scholar 

  24. New Science of Politics, p. 109.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Voegelin is not alone in appreciating the importance of Joachim of Flora. See Herbert Grundmann, Studien über Joachim von Flora (Leipzig, 1927)

    Google Scholar 

  26. Ernesto Buonaiuti, Gioacchino da Fiore (Rome, 1931)

    Google Scholar 

  27. Karl Lowith, Meaning in History (Chicago, 1949).

    Google Scholar 

  28. New Science of Politics, pp. 119–120.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Ibid., p. 122.

    Google Scholar 

  30. “Equivalences of Experience and Symbolization in History,” unpublished ms.

    Google Scholar 

  31. “Preliminary Reflections on the Open Society: Bergson, Popper, Voegelin,” p. 21.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Harold J. Laski, Faith, Reason and Civilization: An Essay in Historical Analysis (New York, 1944), p. 184.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Ibid., p. 51.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Ibid., p. 143.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Voegelin is by no means alone in recognizing the phenomenon of gnosticism. See Michael Polanyi, The Logic of Liberty (Chicago, 1951). In part he says, “Modern totalitarianism is a consummation of the conflict between religion and scepticism. It solves the conflict by embodying our heritage of moral passions in a framework of modern materialistic purposes. The conditions for such an outcome were not present in the age of antiquity before Christianity had set alight new vast moral hopes in the heart of mankind.” p. 110.

    Google Scholar 

  36. B. F. Skinner, Beyond Freedom and Dignity (New York, 1971), pp. 213–215.

    Google Scholar 

  37. C. S. Lewis, The Abolition of Man (New York, 1947), pp. 37–39.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Ibid., pp. 40–41.

    Google Scholar 

  39. “American society, like the great vital societies of the past, was created and maintained by the belief in the universal validity of… objective standards…. Society had not created these standards and, hence, could not abolish them…. The standards were the human formulation of the objective nature of things…. In brief, society was believed to be embedded in, and guided by, self-evident truths, rational and moral, from which society derived whatever truth was to be found in its thought and action…. “It is emphatically not the conception that prevails in America today. In the prevailing view of social life, nothing precedes and transcends society…. A society conceived so as to find the standards for its thought and action only within itself becomes the final arbiter of all things human. The objective criteria of excellence through which civilized man has learned to distinguish a work of art from trash, craftsmanship from shoddiness; scholarship from pretentious sophistication, a good man from a scoundrel, a statesman from a demagogue, greatness from mediocrity — these vital distinctions are blurred if not obliterated by the self-sufficient preferences of the crowd… what the crowd desires and tolerates becomes the ultimate standard of what is good, true, beautiful, useful and wise. What you can get away with, then is morally permitted; what you can get accepted in the market place… becomes the test of truth; art is what people like; what can be sold is useful; and what people will vote for is sound. The honest man and the scoundrel, the scholar and the charlatan, the artist and the hack, the statesman and the demagogue live side by side, and it is not always easy to tell which is which.” Hans Morgenthau, The Purpose of American Politics (New York, 1960), pp. 223–225.

    Google Scholar 

  40. “On the Modern Mind,” Encounter, XXIV (May, 1965), p. 8.

    Google Scholar 

  41. The Logic of Liberty, op. cit., pp. 105–106. It is impossible to do justice to the profundity of Polanyi’s analysis in such a brief reference to his work. Readers are referred to his Personal Knowledge: Towards A Post-Critical Philosophy (Chicago, 1958), for an important attempt to overcome the contemporary epistemological crisis.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Totalitarianism (New York, 1968), p. 474.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Quoted by Hannah Arendt, On Violence (New York, 1969), p. 12.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Personal Knowledge, op. cit., pp. 244–245.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1974 Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, Netherlands

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Hallowell, J.H. (1974). Liberalism and the Open Society. In: Germino, D., Von Beyme, K. (eds) The Open Society in Theory and Practice. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-2056-5_8

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-2056-5_8

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-247-1630-2

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-010-2056-5

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics