Skip to main content

Functions

  • Chapter

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science ((BSPS,volume 27))

Abstract

The notion of function is not all there is to teleology, although it is sometimes treated as though it were. Function is not even the central, or paradigm, teleological concept. But it is interesting and important; and it is still not as well understood as it should be, considering the amount of serious scholarship devoted to it during the last decade or two. Let us hope this justifies my excursion into these murky waters.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Richard Sorabji, ‘Function’, Philosophical Quarterly 14 (1964), 290.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Morton Beckner, The Biological Way of Thought (New York, 1959), Ch. 6.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Beckner gives an alternative formulation in which we can speak of activities as having functions, instead of things. I have abbreviated it here for convenience and clarity. The logical points are the same.

    Google Scholar 

  4. John Canfield, Teleological Explanations in Biology’, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 14 (1964).

    Google Scholar 

  5. Morton Beckner, ‘Function and Teleology’, Journal of the History of Biology 2 (1969), reprinted above pp. 197–212.

    Google Scholar 

  6. As before, Beckner gives an alternative formulation so that we can speak either of a thing or of an activity having a function. My treatment will be limited to things, but again the logical points are the same.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Beckner seems to suggest (p. 207, top) that F must be an activity of the whole system 5, which, of course, would conflict with part of 3. But his illustration, reproduced below, suggests the phrasing I have used here.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Carl Hempel, ‘The Logic of Functional Analyses’, in L. Gross (ed.), Symposium on Sociological Theory (New York, 1959).

    Google Scholar 

  9. Hugh Lehman, ‘Functional Explanations in Biology’, Philosophy of Science 32 (1965).

    Google Scholar 

  10. Sorabji, op cit.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Francisco J. Ayala, ‘Teleological Explanation in Evolutionary Biology’, Philosophy of Science 37 (1970).

    Google Scholar 

  12. Michael E. Ruse, ‘Function Statements in Biology’, Philosophy of Science 38 (1971).

    Google Scholar 

  13. This is not to abandon, or even modify, the previous distinction between functions and goals: the point can be made in this form only given the distinction. Nevertheless, support is provided for the analysis I am presenting here by the fact that the ‘in order to’ of goal-directedness can be afforded a parallel treatment. For that parallel treatment see my paper ‘Explanation and Teleology’, in the June 1972 issue of Philosophy of Science.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Canfield, op. cit., p. 295.

    Google Scholar 

  15. It is sometimes urged that this sort of thing is all a teleological explanation is asserting; this is all ‘why?’ asks in these contexts.

    Google Scholar 

  16. I take the other forms to be essentially equivalent and subject, mutatis mutandis, to the same explication.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Of course, it follows that the notion of a reason offered in one of the alternative formulations is the standard conversational one as well: the reason it exploded was that is got too hot.

    Google Scholar 

  18. The qualification ‘causal’ here serves merely to indicate that this is not the purely inferential sense of ‘consequence’. I am not talking about the result or consequence of an argument — e.g., necessary conditions for the truth of a set of premises. The precise construction of ‘consequence’ appropriate here will become clear below.

    Google Scholar 

  19. It is worth recalling here that ‘is there’ can only sometimes, but not usually, be rendered ‘exists (at all)’. So, contrary to many accounts, what is being explained, and what Z is the result of, can very often not be characterized as ‘that X exists’ simpliciter.

    Google Scholar 

  20. It is often claimed that the asymmetry is temporal, but there are many difficulties with this view. Douglas Gasking, in ‘Causation and Recipes’, Mind (Oct., 1955), attempts to account for it in terms of manipulability with some success. But manipulability is even less generally applicable than time order, so, as far as I know, the problem remains.

    Google Scholar 

  21. The following considerations are intended primarily as support for the entire analysis considered whole. Since (a) has already been examined extensively, however, I have biased the argument slightly to emphasize (b).

    Google Scholar 

  22. The primary discussions of this sort I have in mind are those in Charles Taylor’s Explanation of Behavior and the literature to which it has given rise.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Of course the advantage is not always stated explicitly; ‘I chose American because of its five-across seating’. But for it to be selection of the sort described here, as opposed to mere discrimination, something like an advantage must be at least implicit.

    Google Scholar 

  24. This is a version of the old problem about the tension between rationality and freedom.

    Google Scholar 

  25. This formulation is at best very clumsy and misleading. The matter is much more complicated than this and cannot easily be put in a form suitable for this context. The point is adequately made merely by drawing attention to the fact that conscious and natural selection both provide consequence-etiologies.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Sorabji, op. cit., p. 290.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Including the conveyor-belt case in this manner was clearly a mistake: it is better viewed as a derivative case with no close parallel among natural functions. As it stands it violates (F): it does not have a consequence-etiology, the ripple did not get there because of what it does. It can be included, as a derivative, only by taking advantage of the rich causal possibilities of an intentional context. If we can justify not eliminating the ripple by appeal to its virtue as a sorting device, then with the same utilities, there are circumstances (of availability, relative cost and so forth) in which I could justify including the ripple in the original design. So I can say that, ceteris paribus, the ripple would have come to be there because of what it does, if it had not gotten there fortuitously. We might call this a subjunctive consequence-etiology; but in any case it is a peculiar relative, not a paradigm.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Again, it is worth pointing out that ‘partly’ here does not indicate that ‘because’, when not so qualified, represents a sufficient condition relationship. It merely serves to indicate that more than one thing plays an explanatorily relevant role in this particular case. More than one thing must be mentioned to answer adequately the functional ‘why?’ question in this context. But that answer, as usual, need not provide a sufficient condition for the occurrence of X.

    Google Scholar 

  29. See for example p. 101 ff of J. Hosper, An Introduction to Analytical Philosophy, Prentice Hall, New York, 1953.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Neither of James’ ‘definitions’ of ‘going round’ represent anything anybody ever meant by ‘A is going round B’. The missing feature — represented above by ‘E’ — which is usually present and not explicitly referred to is a commonly accepted fixed reference frame to which one of the parties is relatively firmly attached. Without this the issue simply is formally irresolvable.

    Google Scholar 

  31. The kinds of advantage relevant here are much more narrowly circumscribed than is commonly thought. E.g., tidiness of the analysis is not a relevant advantage. On the other hand it would be relevant to argue that, e.g., calling something an ‘F’ which does not have property E is systematically misleading. But even here we have some choices: we could simply insist that ‘F’ is not applicable in such cases, or we could say we have to clearly distinguish kinds of F.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1976 D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, Holland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Wright, L. (1976). Functions. In: Topics in the Philosophy of Biology. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol 27. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-1829-6_10

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-1829-6_10

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-277-0596-9

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-010-1829-6

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics