Skip to main content

Changes in the Social and Intellectual Organisation of the Sciences: Professionalisation and the Arithmetic Ideal

  • Chapter
The Social Production of Scientific Knowledge

Part of the book series: Sociology of the Sciences A Yearbook ((SOSC,volume 1))

Abstract

The ontological and sociological corollaries of epistemological stances have recently been emphasised by Bhaskar in his critique of phenomenalism (1). Views as to the nature of scientific knowledge, he points out, involve certain assumptions about the nature of the world and the nature of a society which produces that knowledge. While logically necessary connections between ontological, epistemological and sociological commitments such as those traced by Bhaskar need not occur empirically, in the sense that particular groups adhere to a logically coherent set of beliefs, there are certain combinations of commitments, types of knowledge and patterns of social organisation which are more empirically likely than alternative combinations. The institutionalisation of a particular theoretical ideal in the sciences has sociological consequences which affect the future production of knowledge. Furthermore, that institutionalisation itself occurs under particular social circumstances which might not be so favourable to alternative theoretical ideals. While, then, not being directly concerned with the mutual relations of aspects of philosophical doctrines and systems, a major focus of the sociology of the sciences should, I suggest, be to consider how particular social arrangements are consonant with particular theoretical ideals and lead to the production of particular types of knowledge.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes and References

  1. See Roy Bhaskar, A Realist Theory of Science, Leeds: Leeds Books, 1975, pp. 16–57.

    Google Scholar 

  2. This term is taken from Georgescu-Roegen’s discussion of ‘arithmomorphism’ and Harré’s analysis of the Newtonian general conceptual system. It refers to the belief that scientific knowledge is essentially arithmetic, i.e., its elements are “discretely distinct as a single number in relation to the infinity of all others”. Concepts which cannot be analysed in terms of simple arithmetic continua are not considered scientific in this view. See Georgescu-Roegen, N., The Entropy Law and the Economic Process, Harvard University Press, 1971, pp. 14

    Google Scholar 

  3. Georgescu-Roegen, N., The Entropy Law and the Economic Process, Harvard University Press, 1971, pp. 25–52

    Google Scholar 

  4. Harré, R., Matter and Method, London: Macmillan, 1964, pp. 8–58.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Bhaskar, op. cit., 1975, Note 1, pp. 64–126

    Google Scholar 

  6. cf. Georgescu-Roegen, op. cit., 1971, Note 2, pp. 25–59

    Google Scholar 

  7. cf. Georgescu-Roegen, op. cit., 1971, Note 2, pp. 114–139.

    Google Scholar 

  8. cf. Böhme, G., W. v. d. Daele and W. Krohn, ‘Finalisation in Science’, Social Science Information 15, 1976.

    Google Scholar 

  9. See also the application of the ‘finalisation thesis’ to the field of cancer research by Rainer Hohlfeld: Cognitive and Institutional Determinants Directing Science, the case of Biomedical Research’, paper presented at a PAREX-IAS meeting, Vienna, July, 1976.

    Google Scholar 

  10. For one expression of this belief see: Norbert Elias, The Sciences: towards a theory’, in R. D. Whitley (ed.), Social Processes of Scientific Development, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1974.

    Google Scholar 

  11. See also: Richard Whitley, The Sociology of Scientific Work and the History of Scientific Developments’, in S. S. Blume (ed.), New Perspectives in the Sociology of Science, New York, and London: John Wiley, 1977.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Elias, op. cit., 1974, Note 3.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Pierre Bourdieu, ‘The Specificity of the Scientific Field and the Social Conditions of the Progress of Reason’, Social Science Information 14, 1975, pp. 19–47.

    Google Scholar 

  14. cf. Pierre Bourdieu, op. cit., 1975, Note 4

    Google Scholar 

  15. J. R. Ravetz, Scientific Knowledge and Its Social Problems, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1971, pp. 37–53. Collins has linked the development of professional and bureaucratic types of organisation in the sciences to differences in task uncertainty and co-ordination difficulties in an interesting way but does not consider how theoretical ideals can vary and affect these processes.

    Google Scholar 

  16. See: Collins, R., Conflict Sociology, London: Academic Press, 1975, pp. 506–523.

    Google Scholar 

  17. cf. e.g. Terence Johnson, Professions and Power, London, Macmillan, 1972

    Google Scholar 

  18. H. M. Vollmer and D. L. Mills (eds.), Professionalisation, Englewood Cliffs, N. J.: Prentice Hall, 1966

    Google Scholar 

  19. J. A. Jackson (ed.), Professions and Professionalisation, Cambridge University Press, 1970. Krohn has developed a useful contrast between Intellectuals’ and professionals’ as careeer types in contemporary science and emphasised the historicity of present forms of organisation.

    Google Scholar 

  20. See Roger Krohn, The Social Shaping of Science, Westport, Conn, and London: Greenwood Press, 1971, pp. 153–161;

    Google Scholar 

  21. Bourdieu has distinguished cultural and social capital as well as economic capital. See Pierre Bourdieu and J.-C. Passeron, La reproduction: éléments pour une théorie du système d’enseignement, Paris: Editions de Minuit, 1970, pp. 90–129

    Google Scholar 

  22. Bourdieu, P., Luc Boltanski and Monique de Saint Martin, ‘Les Stratégies de reconversion: les classes sociales et le système d’enseignement’, Social Science Information 12, 1973, pp. 61–113.

    Google Scholar 

  23. See also: Bourdieu, P., op. cit., 1975, Note 4.

    Google Scholar 

  24. As Bourdieu says, accumulated scientific resources increase the cost of entry to the competitive struggle, Bourdieu, op. cit., 1975, Note 4, p. 33.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Much of this paragraph is similar to Bourdieu’s views on science. However, he does not consider the nature of the sciences or their ideals in discussing scientific authority, Bourdieu, op. cit., 1975, Note 4.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Elias, op. cit., 1974, Note 3

    Google Scholar 

  27. Georgescu-Roegen, op. cit., 1971, Note 2

    Google Scholar 

  28. C. F. A. Pantin, The Relations Between the Sciences, Cambridge University Press, 1968, Ch. 1.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Jenkin has suggested that some of the influence of Mach’s phenomenalism on quantum physics may be due to its ‘success’ in assisting Boltzmann’s statistical mechanics to reinstate arithmomorphism and mechanics in thermodynamics. See Phyllis Jenkin, Structure and Contradiction in Scientific Development: the Case of Nicholas Georgescu-Roegen and the Entropy Law, unpublished M.Sc. Thesis, Manchester University, 1975, pp. 11–22

    Google Scholar 

  30. Phyllis Jenkin, Structure and Contradiction in Scientific Development: the Case of Nicholas Georgescu-Roegen and the Entropy Law, unpublished M.Sc. Thesis, Manchester University, 1975, pp. 100–109

    Google Scholar 

  31. See also Georgescu-Roegen, op. cit., 1971, Note 2, Chs. 5, 6, 7

    Google Scholar 

  32. P. Forman, ‘Weimar Culture, Causality and Quantum Theory, 1981–1927: adaptation by German Physicists and Mathematicians to a hostile intellectual environment’, Historical Studies in the Physical Sciences 3, 1971.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Pantin, op. cit., 1968, Note 11, pp. 17–25.

    Google Scholar 

  34. ibid., p. 18.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Georgescu-Roegen, op. cit., 1971, Note 2, p. 123.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Rom Harré, Matter and Method, London: Macmillan, 1964.

    Google Scholar 

  37. ibid., p. 97.

    Google Scholar 

  38. ibid., p. 112.

    Google Scholar 

  39. ibid., p. 17.

    Google Scholar 

  40. ibid., p. 13.

    Google Scholar 

  41. ibid., p. 35

    Google Scholar 

  42. see Alan Coddington ‘The Rationale of General Equilibrium Theory’, Economic Inquiry 13, 1975, pp. 539–558 for a detailed discussion of General Equilibrium Theory

    Google Scholar 

  43. also Georgescu-Roegen, op. cit., 1971, Note 2, passim for economics in general.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Georgescu-Roegen, op. cit., 1971, Note 2, pp. 14–15

    Google Scholar 

  45. Georgescu-Roegen, op. cit., 1971, Note 2, pp. 44–47.

    Google Scholar 

  46. ibid., p. 15.

    Google Scholar 

  47. A well known example in sociology is H. L. Zetterberg, On Theory and Verification in Sociology, Totowa, N. J.: Bedminster Press, 1963.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Trevor Pinch, ‘What Does a Proof Do If It Does Not Prove? A Study of the Social Conditions and Metaphysical Devisions Leading to David Bohm and John von Neumann failing to communicate in Quantum Physics’, in this volume, pp. 171–215.

    Google Scholar 

  49. cf. Böhme et al., op. cit., 1976, Note 2b.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Bhaskar, op. cit., 1975, Note 1, pp. 21–24.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Elias, op. cit., 1974, Note 3, p. 28.

    Google Scholar 

  52. idem.

    Google Scholar 

  53. ibid., p. 29.

    Google Scholar 

  54. cf. R. W. Gerard, ‘Hierarchy, Entitation and Levels’, in L. L. Whyte, A. G. Wilson and D. Wilson (eds.), Hierarchical Structures, New York: Elsevier, 1969, p. 225.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Gerard, op. cit., 1969, Note 31

    Google Scholar 

  56. Pantin, op. cit., 1968, Note 11.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Michael Ruse, The Philosophy of Biology, London: Hutchinson, 1973, p. 162.

    Google Scholar 

  58. cf. C. Lammers, ‘Mono- and Poly-Paradigmatic Developments in Natural and Social Sciences’, in R. D. Whitley (ed.), Social Processes of Scientific Development, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1974

    Google Scholar 

  59. Herminio Martins, ‘The Kuhnian ‘Revolution’ and its Implications for Sociology’, in T. J. Nossiter, A. H. Hanson and Stein Rokkan (eds.), Imagination and Precision in the Social Sciences, London: Faber and Faber, 1972.

    Google Scholar 

  60. Georgescu-Roegen, op. cit., 1971, Note 2, p. 115.

    Google Scholar 

  61. idem.

    Google Scholar 

  62. T. S. Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, Chicago: Chicago University Press, 2nd ed., 1970, pp. 182–184.

    Google Scholar 

  63. For the role this notion played in the Einstein, Podolsky and Rosen ‘paradox’, see C. A. Hooker, ‘The Nature of Quantum Mechanical Reality: Einstein versus Bohr’, in R. G. Colodny (ed), Paradigms and Paradoxes, the Philosophical Challenge of the Quantum Domain, Pittsburgh University Press, 1972

    Google Scholar 

  64. and Trevor Pinch, Hidden Variables, Impossibility Proofs and Paradoxes: a Sociological Study of Non-Relativistic Quantum Mechanics, unpublished M.Sc. Thesis, Manchester University, 1976.

    Google Scholar 

  65. J. C. Gaston, Originality and Competition in Science, Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1974, pp. 62–66.

    Google Scholar 

  66. S. S. Blume, Toward a Political Sociology of Science, New York and London: John Wiley, 1974, pp. 193–214.

    Google Scholar 

  67. These types of competition are discussed in R. D. Whitley, ‘Konkurrenzformen Autonomie und Entwicklungsformen wissenschaftlicher Spezialgebiete’, in Nico Stehr and R. König (eds.), Wissenschaftssoziologie, Köln and Opladen: Westdeutscher Verlag, 1975

    Google Scholar 

  68. R. D. Whitley, ‘Specialty Marginality and Types of Competition in the Sciences’, in P. Gleichmann, Johan Goudsblom and H. Korte (eds.), Human Configurations, Essays in Honour of Norbert Elias, Amsterdam, 1977.

    Google Scholar 

  69. W. O. Hagstrom, The Scientific Community, New York: Basic Books, 1965.

    Google Scholar 

  70. See Alan Bitz, ‘History, Division of Labour and the Information Process in Fundamental Particle Physics’ both in A. Bitz, Andrew McAlpine and R. D. Whitley, The Production, Flow and Use of Information in Different Sciences, London: British Library Report Series, 1975.

    Google Scholar 

  71. A. Bitz, ‘Scientific Research and the Information Process in a Nuclear Physics Laboratory’ both in A. Bitz, Andrew McAlpine and R. D. Whitley, The Production, Flow and Use of Information in Different Sciences, London: British Library Report Series, 1975.

    Google Scholar 

  72. Coddington, op. cit., 1975, Note 21, p. 548.

    Google Scholar 

  73. As Bitz has suggested, see A. Bitz, ‘History, Division of Labour and the Information Process in Fundamental Particle Physics’, in A. Bitz et al., op. cit., 1975, Note 43. A. Bitz, Andrew McAlpine and R. D. Whitley, The Production, Flow and Use of Information in Different Sciences, London: British Library Report Series, 1975

    Google Scholar 

  74. Georgescu-Roegen, op. cit., 1971, Note 2, pp. 97–113.

    Google Scholar 

  75. cf. C. S. Smith, ‘Structural Hierarchy in Inorganic Systems’, in L. L. Whyte, A. Wilson and D. Wilson (eds.), op. cit., 1969.

    Google Scholar 

  76. cf. e.g. L. Rosenfeld, ‘Physics and Metaphsics’, Nature, 181, 1958, p. 658.

    Google Scholar 

  77. Bondi and Gold attempted to derive their steady state theory of the universe which posits continuous creation of matter from what they considered to be incontrovertible philosophical doctrines. In contrast to Bohm’s 1952 paper, this attempt does not seem to have created much of a stir in the literature, outside a small circle in Cambridge and London, until Ryle’s experiments in the 1950’s claimed to disprove it. However, Dingle felt compelled to use his position as President of the Royal Astronomical Society to launch a vitriolic attack on the ‘new cosmology’ in 1953 which suggests Bondi and Gold had had some impact among astronomers. See: H. Bondi and T. Gold, ‘The Steady State Theory of the Expanding Universe, Monthly Notices of the Royal Astronomical Society 108, 1948, pp. 252–270

    Google Scholar 

  78. H. Dingle, ‘Science and Cosmology’, Monthly Notices of the Royal Astronomical Society 113, 1953, pp. 393–407

    Google Scholar 

  79. J. Singh, Modern Cosmology, London: Penguin, 1970, pp. 192–218.

    Google Scholar 

  80. For a sociological analysis of the controversy over the steady state theory see: Ben Martin, The Development and Capitulation of Steady State Cosmology: a Sociological Study of Authority and Conflict in Science, unpublished M.Sc. diss., Manchester University, 1976.

    Google Scholar 

  81. Trevor Pinch has analysed the reception to Bohm’s 1952 paper and his subsequent work in some detail in his M.Sc. Thesis, see T. Pinch., op. cit., 1976, Note 38.

    Google Scholar 

  82. The authority of the formalisms in this dispute and some reasons for elite physicists becoming involved in the ‘hidden variables’ controversy are discussed in Pinch’s paper in the current volume. For some of Bohm’s own reconstructions see: D. Bohm, Causality and Chance in Modern Physics, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1957

    Google Scholar 

  83. and D. Bohm, ‘Science as Perception — Communication’, in Suppe, F., The Structure of Scientific Theories, Urbana, Illinois: University of Illinois Press, 1974.

    Google Scholar 

  84. See also: Hooker, op. cit., 1972, Note 38.

    Google Scholar 

  85. Coddington, op. cit., 1975, Note 21.

    Google Scholar 

  86. Coddington, op. cit., 1975, Note 21, p. 552.

    Google Scholar 

  87. The original is in: Hahn, F., On the Notion of Equilibrium in Economics, Cambridge University Press, 1973.

    Google Scholar 

  88. cf. e.g. Elias, op. cit., 1974., Note 3

    Google Scholar 

  89. Gerard, op. cit., 1969, Note 31

    Google Scholar 

  90. Paul Weiss, ‘The Living System: Determinism Stratified’, in Arthur Koestler, and J. R. Smythies (eds.), Beyond Reductionism, London: Hutchinson, 1969

    Google Scholar 

  91. David Willer and Judith Wilier, Systematic Empiricism, Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1974.

    Google Scholar 

  92. cf. A. Bitz, et al., op. cit., 1975, Note 43, passim.

    Google Scholar 

  93. These types of competition involve controversies over explanatory models and definitions of the central problem of specialties as well as over techniques and research practices, c.f. R. D. Whitley, op. cit., 1975, Note 41.

    Google Scholar 

  94. Five distinct components of scientific activities can be identified. These are: metaphysical, specialty concern, explanatory model, techniques and research practice. In any given activity, these components vary in their degree of clarity and coherence or integration. See: R. Whitley, ‘Components of Scientific Activities, Their Characteristics and Institutionalisation in Specialties and Research Areas’, in Karin Knorr, Hermann Strasser and H. G. Zilian (eds.), Determinants and Controls of Scientific Development, Dordrecht: Reidel, 1975a.

    Google Scholar 

  95. cf. A. Coddington, ‘Positive Economics’, Canadian Journal of Economics 5, 1972, pp. 1–15;

    Google Scholar 

  96. M. Friedman, ‘The Methodology of Positive Economics’, in Essays in Positive Economics, Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1953

    Google Scholar 

  97. P.D. McClelland, Causal Explanation and Model Building in History, Economics and the New Economic History, Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1975, pp. 117–145

    Google Scholar 

  98. S. Latsis, ‘Situational Determinism in Economies’, British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 23, 1972, pp. 207–245

    Google Scholar 

  99. F. Machlup, ‘Theories of the Firm: Marginalist, Behavioural, Managerial’, American Economic Review 57, 1967, pp. 1–33.

    Google Scholar 

  100. cf. Steven Rose, The Conscious Brain, London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson, 1973

    Google Scholar 

  101. Weiss, op. cit., 1969, Note 53.

    Google Scholar 

  102. See, among others, D. Fleming, ‘Emigre Physicists and the Biological Revolution’, in D. Fleming and B. Bailyn (eds.), The Intellectual Migration, Harvard University Press, 1969.

    Google Scholar 

  103. cf. Harré, op. cit., 1964, Note 16, p. 35.

    Google Scholar 

  104. A. Hallam, A Revolution in the Earth Sciences, Oxford University, Oxford University Press, 1973, pp. 103–114.

    Google Scholar 

  105. Elias, op. cit., 1974, Note 3

    Google Scholar 

  106. cf. Georgescu-Roegen, op. cit., 1971, Note 2, appendix G.

    Google Scholar 

  107. See the comparison between the ‘analytical approach’ and the ‘numerical approach’ in constructing and evaluating models of tectonic plate motion in E. R. Oxburgh, ‘Plate Tectonics’, in I.G. Gass, P. J. Smith and R. C. L. Wilson (eds.), Understanding the Earth, Sussex: Artemis Press, 1972, especially pp. 273–285. Other articles in the same book also discuss qualitative problems of ‘fit’ and difficulties of assessing rival accounts.

    Google Scholar 

  108. In some biomedical laboratories we studied, project numbers had recently been instituted by the Medical Research Council in an attempt to monitor scientific work at a more specific level but most scientists had no idea what project they were supposed to be working on and some did not know project numbers existed. Such control procedures were often discussed as ‘accounting fictions’. For a discussion of how different types of science are related to organisational strategies see: R. D. Whitley, ‘Types of Science, Organisational Strategies and Patterns of Work in Research Laboratories in Different Scientific Fields’, paper presented to a PAREX-IAS meeting in Vienna, July, 1976.

    Google Scholar 

  109. cf. e.g. D. Crane, Invisible Colleges, Chicago: Chicago University Press, 1972

    Google Scholar 

  110. M. J. Mulkay, The Social Process of Innovation, London: Macmillan, 1972

    Google Scholar 

  111. M. J. Mulkay, G. N. Gilbert and S. Woolgar, ‘Problem Areas and Research Networks in Science’, Sociology 9, 1975, pp. 187–203

    Google Scholar 

  112. N. Mullins, ‘The Development of a Scientific Specialty: the Phage Group and the Origins of Molecular Biology’, Minerva 10, 1972, pp. 51–82.

    Google Scholar 

  113. cf. N. Tinbergen, ‘Ethology’, in R. Harré (ed.), Scientific Thought, 1900–1960, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1969.

    Google Scholar 

  114. Collins, op. cit., 1975, Note 5, p. 473.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Everett Mendelsohn Peter Weingart Richard Whitley

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1977 D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht-Holland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Whitley, R. (1977). Changes in the Social and Intellectual Organisation of the Sciences: Professionalisation and the Arithmetic Ideal . In: Mendelsohn, E., Weingart, P., Whitley, R. (eds) The Social Production of Scientific Knowledge. Sociology of the Sciences A Yearbook, vol 1. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-1186-0_7

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-1186-0_7

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-277-0776-5

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-010-1186-0

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics