Skip to main content

Economics, Ethics, and Decision Theory

The Problem of Controlling Side Effects

  • Chapter
Principles of Ethical Economy

Part of the book series: Issues in Business Ethics ((IBET,volume 17))

  • 170 Accesses

Abstract

Ethics and economics have the same object of knowledge, if the maximum of value-realization, according to the rank ordering of value-qualities, is understood as the final cause of a theory of universal economics or ethical economy. In addition to the commonality of their final cause and highest good, evidence of the convergence of economics and ethics is also found in the numerous side effects between ethical and economic goods and, therefore, also between ethical and economic assessments of actions. These side effects can be seen, first of all, in the mutual influence of experiences and value-convictions, economic costutility calculations and ethical value judgments, as they have been depicted above. l Economic and ethical assessments of goods do not take place independently of one another, but instead exist in positive and negative side effects, in strengthening or conflicting mutual effects on one another. Secondly, the interchangeability of means and ends and the sublimation phenomenon of the attainment of original goals by reducing them to side effects, which are co-attained in the pursuit of something completely different, prove the ubiquity of the phenomenon of side effects. They show how important the ability to control side effects or externalities is for general ethics, ethical economy, and general economics.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Literatur

  1. Cf. Vom Wesen des Geistigen,” in Gesammelte Schriften, ed. Hans Walter Bähr (Tübingen, 1980), Vol. VI above, Section 3.3, pp. 89–91.

    Google Scholar 

  2. The phenomenon of sinking marginal morality follows from this attenuation of assurance. Cf. Vom Wesen des Geistigen,” in Gesammelte Schriften, ed. Hans Walter Bähr (Tübingen, 1980), Vol. VI below, Section 7.3, pp. 178–81.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Eduard Spranger, “Vom Wesen des Geistigen,” in Gesammelte Schriften, ed. Hans Walter Bähr (Tübingen, 1980), Vol. VI, pp. 305–12. See also Robert Spaemann, “Die Herausforderung.” in Mut zur Erziehung (Stuttgart, 1978). Spaemann — going beyond Spranger — sees the task of education as the explicit observance of personality-forming side effects on the persons being educated. With Spranger, however, the question should be asked whether education can achieve this at all, or whether the side effects of education will not always remain as such.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Cf. Adolf Schönke and Horst Schröder, Strafgesetzbuch: Kommentar, 22nd Ed. (Munich. 1982), pp. 199–204; and Gustav Radbruch, Der Handlungsbegriff in seiner Bedeutung für das Strafrechtssystem (Darmstadt, 1967).

    Google Scholar 

  5. Cf. Gordon Tullock, “An Application of Economics in Biology,” in Toward Liberty (Menlo Park, 1971), Vol. II, p. 391; and Koslowski, Evolution und Gesellschaft (Tübingen, 1984), pp. 49fT.

    Google Scholar 

  6. On the role of imagination in managerial action, see also G. L. S. Shackle, Imagination and the Nature of Choice (Edinburgh, 1979); and pp. 157–58 below.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Jean-Paul Sartre, Existentialism and Humanism, trans. Philip Mairet (London, 1948), p. 37.

    Google Scholar 

  8. G. L. S. Shackle, Imagination and the Nature of Choice, pp. 18 ff.; and Epistemics and Economics (Cambridge, 1972), p. 47: “If we are candid, knowledge of the future is a contradiction in tenus.”

    Google Scholar 

  9. Cf. Max Scheler, Der Formalismus in der Ethik und die materiale Wertethik, 6th Ed. (Bern. 1980), pp. 137.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Annen A. Alchian, Economic Forces at Work (Indianapolis, 1977), p. 17.

    Google Scholar 

  11. The problem corresponds to the theory of the “second best” for conditions of impelfect competition, developed by Richard G. Lipsey and Kelvin Lancaster, “The General Theory of the Second Best,” Review of Economic Studies, 24 (1956), pp. 11–32. If the optimality conditions in a sector of the economy are not met, it can be more efficient to make adjustments in the other sectors that yield solutions that are, when judged by the ideal conditions of perfect competition. “second best.” See also Charles K. Rowley and Alan T. Peacock, Welfare Economics (London. 1975), Chap. 2.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. Cf. Koslowski, Gesellschaft und Staat, pp. 230 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Wolfgang Stegmüller, Problerne und Resultate der Wissenschaftstheorie und Analytischen Philosophie, Vol. I: Personelle Wahrscheinlichkeit und rationale Entscheidung (Berlin. 1973). p. 325.

    Google Scholar 

  14. On the metaphysics of decision theory, see also Patrick Suppes. Probabilistic Metaphysics (Uppsala, 1974).

    Google Scholar 

  15. On probabilism in ethics, see Charles Sainte-Foi, „Du Probabilisme,“ Le Correspondant. 2 (1843), pp. 145–59; Ignaz von Dollinger and Fr. H. Reusch, Geschichte der Moralstreitigkeiten in der römisch-katholischen Kirche (Ntlrdlingen, 1889); and Heinrich Klomps, Tradition und Fortschritt in der Moraltheologie (Bonn, 1963).

    Google Scholar 

  16. On the theory of expected value maximization, see also R. Duncan Luce and Howard Raiffa, Games and Decisions (New York, 1957); and Patrick Suppes, “Decision Theory,” in Paul Edwards, ed., Encyclopedia of Philosophy (New York, 1967), Vol. ü, p. 311.

    Google Scholar 

  17. John Henry Newman, An Essay in Aid ofa Grammar of Assent (London, 1870).

    Google Scholar 

  18. Blaise Pascal, “The Provincial Letters,” trans. Thomas M’Crie, in Mortimer J. Adler. ed.. Great Books of the Western World, 2nd Ed. (Chicago, 1990), Vol. XXX. p. 45.

    Google Scholar 

  19. John Maynard Keynes, A Treatise on Probability (London, 1973), Chap. 26: “The Application of Probability to Conduct.”

    Google Scholar 

  20. On the “paradox of choice,” see Shackle, Imagination and the Nature of Choice. p. 19.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Cf. Henry G. Van Leeuwen, “Certainty in Seventeenth-Century Thought” and Shirley Robin Letwin, “Certainty Since the Seventeenth Century,” in Philip P. Wiener, ed., Dictionary of the History of Ideas (New York, 1968), Vol. I, pp. 304–11 and 312-25; and Helmut Thielicke. Theologische Ethik (Tübingen, 1965), p. 88.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Aeschylus, Prometheus Bound, trans. James Scully and C. John Herington (Oxford. 1975). p. 53. verse 514: “Art is far feebler than Necessity.”

    Google Scholar 

  23. On the School of Salamanca, from an ethical perspective, see Friedrich Stegmüller. „Zur Literaturgeschichte der Salmanticenser Theologen,“ Theologische Revue, 29 (1930). pp. 55–59: and „Die spanischen Handschriften der Salmanticenser Theologen,“ Theologische Revue. 30 (1931), pp. 361-65: 1. T. Mangan, “A Historical Analysis of the Principle of Double Effect.” Theological Studies, 10 (1949), pp. 41–61; and Jozef Ghoos. «L’acte à double effet,» Ephemerides Theologicae Lovanenses, 27 (1951), pp. 30–52. For an economic perspective, see Marjorie GriceHutchinson, The School of Salamanca (Oxford, 1952).

    Google Scholar 

  24. On the problem of actions with double effects, see Peter Knauer, “The Hermeneutic Function of the Principle of Double Effect,” Natural Law Forum, 12 (1967), pp. 132–62; Richard McCormick, “Das Prinzip der Doppelwirkung einer Handlung,” Concilium, 12 (1976), pp. 662–70: R. A. Duff, “Absolute Principles and Double Effect,” Analysis, 36 (1976), pp. 68–80; Joseph M. Boyle, Jr., Germain Grisez, and Olaf Tollefson, Free Choice (Notre Dame. Ind., 1976): Robert Spaemann, “Nebenwirkungen als moralisches Problem.” in Spaemann, Kritik der politischen Utopie (Stuttgart, 1977), pp. 167–82; Boyle, “Toward Understanding the Principle of Double Effect.” Ethics, 90 (1980), pp. 527–38; L. J. McNamara, Direct and Indirect (Ph.D. Thesis, University of Oxford, 1980); 1. L. Mackie, Ethics (London, 1977), pp. 160–68: S. S. Levy. The Doctrine ofthe Double Effect (Ph.D. Thesis, University of Michigan. 1982); G. E. M. Anscombe. “Action. Intention, and ‘Double Effect,’” Proceedings of the American Catholic Philosophical Association. 57 (1983), pp. 12–25. On judgment of consequences, see Rainer Specht, Innovation und Foigelast (Stuttgart, 1972).

    Google Scholar 

  25. On praeter intentionem, see Boyle, “Aquinas on Praeter Intentionem,” Thomist, 42 (1978), pp. 649–65; and M. Müller, Ethik und Recht in der Lehre von der Verantwortlichkeit (Rcgensburg. 1932).

    Google Scholar 

  26. John of Saint Thomas, Cursus Theologicus (Madrid, 1645-56), tom. VI, disp. Xl. a. 6, cap. 39 and 42.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Jean Pierre Gury, Compendium theologiae moralis, 2 vols. (Lyon, 1850): 17th Ed. (1866). tr. I, cap. ü, n. 9.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Cf. above, p. 110.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Boyle, “Toward Understanding the Principle of Double Effect,” p. 537.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Anscombe, “Action, Intention, and ‘Double Effect.’”

    Google Scholar 

  31. On the practical application of the principle of double effect in business ethics, Lebensverllingerung,” in Koslowski, et al., eds., Die Verführung durch das Machbare (Stuttgart, 1983) see below. Section 7.2, pp. 176–77.

    Google Scholar 

  32. For an analysis of the problem of side effects of physicians’ actions and the detennination of the boundaries of physicians’ conduct obligation with the help of the principle of double effect. see Koslowski, “Lebensverllingerung,” in Koslowski, et al., eds., Die Verführung durch das Machbare (Stuttgart, 1983), pp. 83–100.

    Google Scholar 

  33. [Cursus] Collegii Salmanticensis, Cursus Theologicus, tom. 7, tract. Xül, disp. 10, dub. 6. n. 214–47 (Comm. in S. Thomae s. th. II-II, q. 64, a. 7), (= Tractatus de bonitate et malitia actuum humanorum), ed. Domingo de Santa Teresa. See also Mangan, “A Historical Analysis of the Principle of Double Effect.”

    Google Scholar 

  34. Nikolaus Seelhammer, “Doppelwirkung einer Handlung,” Lexikon für Theologie und Kirche (Freiburg, 1959), Vol. Ill, p. 516–17.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2001 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Koslowski, P. (2001). Economics, Ethics, and Decision Theory. In: Principles of Ethical Economy. Issues in Business Ethics, vol 17. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-0956-0_6

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-0956-0_6

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-1-4020-0364-6

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-010-0956-0

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics