Skip to main content

A Normative Account of Temperance

  • Chapter
Passionate Deliberation

Part of the book series: Philosophical Studies in Contemporary Culture ((PSCC,volume 8))

  • 106 Accesses

Abstract

An analysis of temperance must acknowledge that desire is intimately involved with pleasure.1 For both Aristotle and Aquinas there are two realms from which pleasure arises; either the intellect or the sensate aspects of existence. While their detailed account of human nature analyzes these “parts” in a way that gives the impression they are distinct and separate, in fact, there is a very close relationship between these pleasure faculties.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. As Aquinas put it in ST I-II 32.2 ad 3, “desire is chiefly a craving for pleasure.” See also ST II-II 141.3: “Desire denotes an impulse of appetite towards the object of pleasure, and this impulse needs control, which belongs to temperance.”

    Google Scholar 

  2. There are pleasures not attached to bodily functions, namely, the intellective functions which are “desirable in themselves” (NE 7.4.2).

    Google Scholar 

  3. See also, ST II-II 141.4; I-II 60.5; II-II 123.12; and II-II 141.3 where he states, “temperance...is chiefly concerned with those passions that tend towards sensible goods, viz. desire and pleasure.”

    Google Scholar 

  4. Within NE see 1.13.15-20. See also The Rhetoric 1370a 17-27, and Eudemian Ethics 2.1.15-20. In Aquinas see ST I 79-82; also note his Commentary on Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics, trans. C. I. Litzinger. Notre Dame: Dumb Ox Books, 1964, pp. 79–81.

    Google Scholar 

  5. As James Wallace writes in Virtues and Vices, p. 62, the view that holds the virtues as determining the outcome of “two struggling elements” has its point but maintaining this dualism cannot suffice for a philosophical account of human psychology and the virtues today. Rather we must be mindful of our susceptibility to “conceptions that prevent us from seeing how they [sensitive and intellective faculties] interact.”

    Google Scholar 

  6. Kenny, Anthony. Aquinas on Mind. New York: Routledge, Inc., 1993, p. 60. See also The Moral Virtues and Theological Ethics, pp. 66-71, and The Definition of Moral Virtue, pp. 93-104, for examinations of these appetites.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Ambrose also held that regulation of passion should include the intellectual appetite. Book One of De officiis ministrorum assumes an understanding that passions of the mind stand in need of modesty, temperance, and seemliness. “Mental motions” are the particular concern of seemliness (I.98). Even the search for truth must be held to the standard of “what is seemly” (I.122). In the passage where he writes of guarding the pure inner life, he refers to a “sobriety of mind” (I.12). The outward movements are simply indicators of inward attitudes. “For the condition of the mind is often seen in the attitude of the body. For this reason the hidden man of our heart (our inner self) is considered to be either frivolous, boastful, or boisterous, or, on the other hand, steady, firm, pure, and dependable. Thus the movement of the body is a sort of voice of the soul” (I.71). Augustine, also recognizes in The Morals of the Catholic Church, 19.36, both physical and psychological aspects of temperance when he writes that the duty of temperance is to “scorn all bodily delights, and the popular applause, and to turn the whole love to things divine and unseen.” See On the Morals of the Catholic Church, trans. R. Stothert, in Basic Writings of Saint Augustine, ed. Whiney J. Oates, vol. 1, New York: Random House, 1948, p. 337.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Aristotle rules out the need for temperance in response to intellectual desire, the pleasures of which are of a purely mental sort. The intellectual desires include ambition and the love of learning (NE 3.10.2).

    Google Scholar 

  9. See also ST I-II 17.7; 30.1; 59.2; 59.5; II-II 158.8.

    Google Scholar 

  10. For the identification of the intellectual appetite with the will, see ST I 59.4; 82.5; I-II 8.1.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Fabric of Character, p. 6.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Note also a reference regarding the aggressive faculty in which the virtue courage is located. In this question (ST II-II 162), the aggressive faculty which is located in the sensitive appetite, is said to belong instead to the intellective appetite. “Now the irascible may be taken in two ways. First in a strict sense, and thus it is a part of the sensitive appetite,...Secondly, the irascible may be taken in a broader sense, so as to belong also to the intellective appetite....The irascible understood in this broad sense is not distinct from the concupiscible power” (ST II-II 162.3). If the aggressive faculty, which is located with temperance in the sensitive appetite, can be said to be in the intellective appetite indistinguishable from the impulse faculty, then it follows that the same can be said of the impulse faculty, namely, that it is in the intellective appetite.

    Google Scholar 

  13. It should be noted here that Aquinas, in part, follows Augustine in this account of studiousness when he writes: “Augustine says (De morib. eccl. 21): ‘We are forbidden to be curious: and this is a great gift that temperance bestows.’ Now curiosity is prevented by moderate studiousness. Therefore studiousness is a part of temperance” (ST II-II 166.2). Augustine should be recognized as an essential source in prompting Aquinas to explicitly treat this notion of intellectual temperance. In De moribus ecclesiae catholicae 21.38 Augustine writes: “Quamobrem recte etiam curiosi esse prohibemur, quod magnum temperantiae munus est.” See Bauer, Johannes B. Sancti Avreli Avgvstini Opera, 6:7 Corpvs Scriptorvm Ecclesiasticurvm Latinorvm, Vol. 40, ed. Johannes B. Bauer, Vindobonae: Hoelder-Pichler-Tempsky, 1992.

    Google Scholar 

  14. For example, NE 7.4.4 puts the relationship this way, “And hence we class the unrestrained man with the profligate (and the self-restrained with the temperate), but not those who yield to anger or the like, because Unrestraint and Profligacy are related to the same pleasures and pains. But as a matter of fact, although they are related to the same things, they are not related to them in the same way; the profligate acts from choice, the unrestrained man does not.” See also NE 7. sections 3.2; 4.2; 5.9; 7.1; 8.4-5; and 9.5-7.

    Google Scholar 

  15. The passage in full reads: “Now those who against the right principle within them exceed in regard to the latter class of pleasant things, we do not call unrestrained simply, but with a qualification—unrestrained as to money, gain, honour or anger—not merely ‘unrestrained’; because we regard them as distinct from the unrestrained in the strict sense, and only so called by analogy” (NE 7.4.2).

    Google Scholar 

  16. Charles Young refers to “intellectual temperance” in “Aristotle on Temperance,” pp. 541-542. It is a matter of self-knowledge and “consists in a consciousness of one’s place and of the limits that this implies.” On the other hand “moral temperance” is that virtue which concerns self-control rather than self-knowledge. According to Young, Plato presents moral temperance as a product of intellectual temperance. Aristotle’s focus is somewhat different. Intellectual temperance for Aristotle is to “know one’s place in the community of souls;” to realize one’s animality and be properly, or morally oriented toward it.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Roberts, Robert. “Emotions Among the Virtues of the Christian Life,” p. 56.

    Google Scholar 

  18. The Moral Psychology of the Virtues, p. 167.

    Google Scholar 

  19. The Moral Psychology of the Virtues, p. 162.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2001 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Carr, M.F. (2001). A Normative Account of Temperance. In: Passionate Deliberation. Philosophical Studies in Contemporary Culture, vol 8. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-0591-3_4

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-0591-3_4

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-010-3892-8

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-010-0591-3

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics