Advertisement

What Is an Illocutionary Point?

  • Mark Siebel
Part of the Studies in Linguistics and Philosophy book series (SLAP, volume 79)

Abstract

There are many different things a person can do in making an utterance. By uttering “Come on, let’s take part in the twist contest!”, Mia might ask Vincent to dance with her, frighten him because he does not like to dance in public, call his attention to the contest, and so on. One of the tasks of speech act theory is to sort these things out in a satisfactory way. John Searle’s taxonomy is the most famous attempt at classifying an important class of speech acts, namely illocutionary acts.

Keywords

Propositional Content Sincerity Condition Constitutive Rule Illocutionary Force Declarative Class 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Alston, W.P. Illocutionary Acts and Sentence Meaning. Ithaca, and London, 2000.Google Scholar
  2. Ballmer, T. “Probleme der Klassifikation von Sprechakten.” In: G. Grewendorf (ed.). Sprechakttheorie und Semantik. Frankfurt/M., 1979: 247–274.Google Scholar
  3. Davis, W.A. “A Causal Theory of Intending.” In: A.R. Mele (ed.). The Philosophy of Action. Oxford, 1997: 131–148.Google Scholar
  4. Grice, H.P. 1957: “Meaning.” In: Studies in the Way of Words. Cambridge/M. and London, 1989: 213–223. Or. publ. in: The Philosophical Review 66, 377-388.Google Scholar
  5. Humberstone, I.L. “Direction of Fit.” Mind 101 (1992): 59–83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Meggle, G. Grundbegriffe der Kommunikation. 2nd, updated ed. Berlin, and New York, 1997.Google Scholar
  7. Rolf, E. Illokutionäre Kräfte. Opladen, 1997.Google Scholar
  8. Searle, J.R. Speech Acts, Cambridge, 1969.Google Scholar
  9. Searle, J.R. “A Taxonomy of Illocutionary Acts.” In: Expression and Meaning. Cambridge, 1979: 1–29. Or. publ. in: K. Gunderson (ed.). Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science 9: Language, Mind and Knowledge. Minneapolis, 1975: 344-369.Google Scholar
  10. Searle, J.R. lntentionality, Cambridge, 1983.Google Scholar
  11. Searle, J.R. “Meaning, Communication, and Representation.” In: R. Grandy, and R. Warner (eds.). Philosophical Grounds of Rationality: Intentions, Categories, Ends. Oxford, 1986: 209–226.Google Scholar
  12. Searle, J.R. “Response: Meaning, lntentionality, and Speech Acts.” In: E. Lepore, and R. van Gulick (eds.). John Searle and His Critics. Cambridge/M., 1991: 81–102.Google Scholar
  13. Searle, J.R. The Construction of Social Reality. London, 1995.Google Scholar
  14. Searle, JR., and D. Vanderveken. Foundations of Illocutionary Logic. Cambridge, 1985.Google Scholar
  15. Siebel, M. “Searle’s Representing Account of Illocutionary Acts and Its Weak Spots.” In: L. Lundsten, A. Siitonen, and B. Österman (eds.). Communication and Intelligibility (Acta Philosophica Fennica 69). Helsinki, 2001:97–111.Google Scholar
  16. Stegmüller, W. Theorie und Erfahrung. Berlin, 1970.Google Scholar
  17. Ulkan, M. Zur Klassifikation von Sprechakten. Tübingen, 1992.Google Scholar
  18. Vanderveken, D. “What is an Illocutionary Force?” In: M. Dascal (ed.). Dialogue An Interdisciplinary Approach. Amsterdam, 1985: 181–204.Google Scholar
  19. Vanderveken, D. Meaning and Speech Acts I: Principles of Language Use. Cambridge, 1990.Google Scholar
  20. Vanderveken, D. Meaning and Speech Acts II: Formal Semantics of Success and Satisfaction. Cambridge, 1991.Google Scholar
  21. Vanderveken, D. “A Complete Formulation of a Simple Logic of Elementary Illocutionary Acts.” In: S.L. Tsohatzidis (ed.). Foundations of Speech Act Theory. London, and New York, 1994: 99–131.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2002

Authors and Affiliations

  • Mark Siebel

There are no affiliations available

Personalised recommendations