Skip to main content

Woman is not a Rational Animal: On Aristotle’s Biology of Reproduction

  • Chapter
Discovering Reality

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 161))

Abstract

The conservatism of Aristotle has long been a subject of discussion among philosophers. His belief in the superiority of the male sex, however, while it has not entirely escaped their notice,1 has not thus far been carefully examined. In a path-breaking article,2 Christine Garside-Allen brought to our attention the possibility that the work of Aristotle is in fact the study of the male human, rather than the human species, and pointed to the possibility that this may be true of most influential philosophers. This task of hers was an explicit necessity because in most cases philosophers’ ideas about sex difference are not now widely known. In what are known as the “main” theories of various political or moral philosophers, distinctions of sex are not often mentioned, or they are alluded to briefly in a way that makes them appear inessential to the theory. I want to suggest that the reason for this is not that their views of sexual differences are incidental to the theory but that in almost every case they are considered to be a question which is prior to general ethical or political issues. This may be the case regardless of whether or not these views are actually discussed in any detail. For most of these thinkers, however, there will be found a treatise of some sort on the subject. It has been the practice of twentieth-century scholars and educators in the face of the greater equality of women, simply to disregard these works, which they view as minor or peripheral, or perhaps crankish, like Berkeley’s late essays on the value of tar water. Unfortunately, this policy is not soundly based on the actual role of these views in most political and social philosophy.

Aristotle . . . pretends that women are but monsters. Who would not believe it, upon the authority of so renowned a personage? To say, it is an impertinence; would be, to choak his supposition too openly.

If a woman, (how learned soever she might be), had wrote as much of men, she would have lost all her credit; and men would have imagined it sufficient, to have refuted such a foppery; by answering, that it must be a woman, or a fool, that had said so.

From De l’egalité des deux sexes (Paris, 1673) François Poulain de la Barre (1647–1723), anonymously translated into English as The Woman as Goodas the Man (London, 1677).

All references to Aristotle are to The Works of Aristotle, ed. by J. A. Smith and W. D. Ross (Oxford University Press: Oxford, 1908–1952).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 179.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. In his preface to the 1910 translation of De Generatione Animalium, Arthur Piatt remarks on the “curious depreciation of the female sex.”

    Google Scholar 

  2. Garside-Allen, Christine, ‘Can a Woman be Good in the Same Way as a Man?’, Dialogue 10 (1971), 534–544.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  3. Garside-Allen, p. 536.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Garside-Allen, p. 537.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Randall, J. H., Aristotle (New York, 1960), pp. 220, 242.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Aristotle makes, for example, the ingenious argument that this does not in fact explain ressemblance, which it was intended to do, for “if really flesh and bones are composed of fire and the like elements, the semen would come rather from the elements than anything else, for how can it come from their composition? Yet without this composition there would be no resemblance. If again something creates this composition later, it would be this that would be the cause of the ressemblance, not the coming of the semen from every part of the body.” (722 a 34)

    Google Scholar 

  7. Randall, p. 41.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Randall, p. 46.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Darwin wrote “Linnaeus and Cuvier have been my two gods, though in very different ways, but they were mere schoolboys to old Aristotle” (Life and Letters, vol. iii, p. 252.)

    Google Scholar 

  10. Even Randall, writing in 1960, remarks on Aristotle’s errors in connexion with spontaneous generation, and refers to his “generally correct” theory!

    Google Scholar 

  11. Hintikka, Jaakko, “On the Ingredients of an Aristotelian Science”, Noûs 6, 55–69 MR 72.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Hintikka, p. 59.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Hintikka, p. 58.

    Google Scholar 

  14. “The object of investigation is always an end, or function of the subject matter: what that kind of thing does, how it operates. And the problems of that science are how everything in the subject matter, all the facts there displayed, are related to and involved in that function. The inquiry thus seeks to analyze the factors involved in a certain function. Hence it is important at the outset to establish norms: in the De Anima, knowing; in the Ethics, the “prudent” or intelligent man. The norm is always a perfected activity,...” Randall, p. 52.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Should it be doubted that such a concept reflects any significant tendancy, consider the admiration of Nietzsche for Greek civilization, where “Woman had no other mission than to produce beautiful, strong, bodies, in which the father’s character lived on as unbrokenly as possible”. ‘Human All Too Human’, in The Complete Works of Nietzsche, trans. O. Levy (New York, 1964), p. 238, #259.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Randall, p. 52.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Grene, Marjorie, ‘Aristotle and Modern Biology’, Journal of the History of Ideas 33, 395–424.

    Google Scholar 

  18. It has been objected to me that this entire paper is a mistake, on the ground that terms like “active” and “passive”, “masculine” and “feminine”, and even “inferior” and “superior”, are mere metaphysical terms, and have nothing to do with actual inferiority and superiority. In this connection, it may be noticed that the translator, Arthur Platt, remarks that throughout De Generatione Animalium “the male” and “the female” are in the neuter, and their force cannot be conveyed precisely in English. These tortured ideas are the basis of the notion that Aristotle is not really a sexist, and that he meant only that “the female” (in the neuter, of course) was not a bearer of the highest form of rationality, and not necessarily that actual females (in the female) were such. Whatever this may mean, it’s supposed to be a good thing for women. But if this were the case, why does Aristotle go ahead and conclude that women are in fact inferior, and ought to have an inferior position in society? Perhaps it is only “the female” or “the female principle” he meant to exclude from political life. If so, actual women have nothing to worry about. Leaving their “principles” at home, they may presumably involve themselves in politics as men do!

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2003 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Lange, L. (2003). Woman is not a Rational Animal: On Aristotle’s Biology of Reproduction. In: Harding, S., Hintikka, M.B. (eds) Discovering Reality. Synthese Library, vol 161. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-0101-4_1

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-0101-4_1

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-1-4020-1319-5

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-010-0101-4

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics