Skip to main content

Discussions Concerning Unity and Multiplicity

  • Chapter
Philosophy of Arithmetic

Part of the book series: Edmund Husserl ((HUCO,volume 10))

  • 1150 Accesses

Abstract

In the last chapters we have settled all essential questions bearing upon the understanding of the psychological origination and content of the concepts multiplicity and unity, of the determinate number concepts, as well as of the concepts equal, more and less. Our next task will be to confirm the insight won by resolving the difficulties that have been discovered in these concepts, and that seem to involve us in inextricable contradictions and subtleties.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 349.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 449.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 449.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Essay, Book II, ch. 16, sect 1.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Ibid., sect. 2. LE

    Google Scholar 

  3. G. Berkeley, A Treatise Concerning the Principles of Human Knowledge. The works of George Berkeley, collected by A. C. Fraser, Vol. I, Oxford 1871, sect. 12, 13, 118-121 (where Locke is criticized without being mentioned by name).

    Google Scholar 

  4. Book II, ch. 12, § 3, Opera philosophica, Erdmann, p. 238. (I have quoted the translation of the New Essays by Peter Remnant and Jonathan Bennett, New York: Cambridge University Press, 1989, p. 145. DW)

    Google Scholar 

  5. Opera philosophica, Erdmann, p. 435. In the year 1684 he still ranked number among the concepts that are common to several senses. Cp. Erdmann, p. 79.

    Google Scholar 

  6. De corpore, VII, 7, cited from J. J. Baumann, Die Lehren von Raum, Zeit und Mathematik, Vol. I, p. 274.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Cp. G. Frege, Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik, p. 38. The sentences following in the text are taken from the same work, p. 57, where they stand, however, in a different context of thought. But since our concern is precisely with the Ideas [Ideen] expressed there, we insert them here.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Cp. the remark by J. F. Herbart, Psychologie als Wissenschaft, Part II, top page 162.

    Google Scholar 

  9. As is well known, the use of 1 in calculation, which was fairly obvious, already belongs to the pre-scientific period of arithmetic, whereas for the introduction of the 0, presupposing a relatively highly developed arithmetical understanding, the wisdom of the Hindus is to be thanked. As M. Cantor, Vorlesungen über Geschichte der Mathematik, Vol. 1, Leipzig 1880, p. 159, observes, the Pythagoreans still held the one not to be a number.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Op. cit., p. 57. LE

    Google Scholar 

  11. J. F. Herbart, Op. cit., Part il, p. 162.

    Google Scholar 

  12. W. Volkmann, Lehrbuch der Psychologie, Vol. II, 3rd Edition., Cöthen 1885, p. 114.

    Google Scholar 

  13. De arte combinatoria, Opera phüosophica, ed. J. E. Erdmann, p. 8.

    Google Scholar 

  14. After these discussions it may seem as if the division of names into abstract and general, upon which, e.g., J. St. Mill (Logic, Book I, ch. II, § 4) places such great weight, is one that is useless because it cannot be implemented. If, however, we define an abstract name as a name of an abstract concept, but a general name as a name of the respective conceptual objects, then in each case it is immediately decidable from the sense of the context whether a name is being used as an abstract or general one, in spite of its equivocal character.

    Google Scholar 

  15. This was one consideration that led us, in cases where we remained within the domain of concrete phenomena, to prefer the names “totality” or “group,” and, where we passed over to general concepts, to choose the names “multiplicity,” etc. (Compare also the “Note” on p. 100 above.)

    Google Scholar 

  16. See J. J. Baumann, Die Lehren von Raum, Zeit und Mathematik, Vol. I, p. 242.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Op. cit., p. 161. In the same sense, Fr. Ueberweg, System der Logik, 5th Edition., Bonn 1882, p. 129, explains: “The numeralia can be understood only on the basis of concept formation, for they presuppose the subsumption of homogeneous objects under the relevant concept.” (Cp. also Ibid., p. 141)

    Google Scholar 

  18. Cp. the quotation on p. 51 above.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Op. cit., p. 50.

    Google Scholar 

  20. That is also why the general terms which are based on the concepts of multiplicity and number (e.g., “group”) for the most part incidentally connote the sameness of the objects grasped together. Still, this is least true in the case of the name “totality,” which in this respect also possesses a certain advantage.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Op. cit., p. 50. LE

    Google Scholar 

  22. J. St. Mill, A System of Logic, Book II, ch. VI, § 3. Compare also W. St. Jevons, The Principles of Science, p. 159; and, further, the citations from Kroman following below, from Unsere Naturerkenntnis, Copenhagen 1883. — This view is, moreover, also widely held among mathematicians.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Logique Algorithmique, Liège/Brussels 1877, p. 33. (Also appearing in Vol. I of the Revue Philosophique.) Delboeuf also stands close to Mill in other respects. A few lines further we read: “Number is the scientific expression of the sensible idea of plurality.”

    Google Scholar 

  24. K. Kroman, Unsere Naturerkenntnis, pp. 104–105. Kroman is substantially influenced by the views of A. Lange. (Cp. Chapter II of the present work.)

    Google Scholar 

  25. Cp. Frege, op. cit., pp. 41ff.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Cp. the quotations on pp. 133-134 of the present work.

    Google Scholar 

  27. A Treatise on Human Nature, Part II, sect. II. In the Green and Grose edition, Vol. I, pp. 337-338.

    Google Scholar 

  28. J. J. Baumann, Die Lehren von Raum, Zeit und Mathematik, Vol. II, pp. 669–670.

    Google Scholar 

  29. For easily understandable reasons mathematicians tend to explain the unit precisely in this sense. Cp. P. du Bois-Reymond, Die allgemeine Functionentheorie, Vol. I, pp. 48 and 49, where the confusion with the unit in the sense of #2 clearly stands out. Cp. also Frege, Op. cit., p. 66.

    Google Scholar 

  30. This projected volume of The Philosophy of Arithmetic was never completed as such. But see Essay III. DW

    Google Scholar 

  31. Cp. the quotation on p. 120.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Cp. the Appendix to Part I, below.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Also the name “unification” and the verb “unify” (to combine into a whole) have arisen in this way.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Principles of Human Knowledge, section 12, emphasis added. Cp. also New Theory of Vision, section 109, Fraser ed., Vol. I, p. 25.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Cp. also Frege, Op. cit., p. 58.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Chr. Sigwart, Logik, Vol. II, p. 42.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Lehrbuch zur Einleitung in die Philosophie, Hamburg and Leipzig 1883, § 118.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Op. cit., p. 186.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2003 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Husserl, E. (2003). Discussions Concerning Unity and Multiplicity. In: Philosophy of Arithmetic. Edmund Husserl, vol 10. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-0060-4_9

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-0060-4_9

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-1-4020-1603-5

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-010-0060-4

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics