Skip to main content

Critical Developments

  • Chapter
Philosophy of Arithmetic

Part of the book series: Edmund Husserl ((HUCO,volume 10))

  • 1156 Accesses

Abstract

The shortest answer to the question about what kind of unification is present in the totality lies in a direct reference to the phenomena. And here we truly are concerned with ultimate facts. But we are not thereby relieved of the task of considering this kind of combination more carefully, in order to bring into relief its characteristic differences from other kinds, especially since false characterizations and confusions of it with other species of relations have been an all too common occurrence. To this end we shall test a series of possible theories, some of which have actually been advanced. Each of these theories characterizes the collective unification in a different way and, in relation thereto, seeks also to explain in a different way the origin of the concepts multiplicity and number.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 349.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 449.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 449.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Perhaps some readers will be surprised at my indecisive language here, where confirming examples for even considerably larger numbers are so easily adduced. As a matter of fact, in playing dominoes, for example, we grasp groups of ten to twelve dots with one glance. Indeed, we even assess their number with total immediacy. It must be observed, however, that in such cases we can speak neither of an actual colligating nor of an actual enumerating. The number name is here directly associated with the characteristic sensuous appearance, and is then recalled on each occasion by means of that appearance without any conceptual mediation. With groups that large, as everyone can test, a direct and authentic collection and enumeration is an impossibility. In the case of very small groups, of two or three objects, the matter stands in doubt because the successive apprehensions of the elements could ensue so quickly that they themselves would escape focused attention. Therefore the cautious manner of speaking in the text.

    Google Scholar 

  2. By overlooking this circumstance, the most recent analyst of the number concept, W. Brix, has also fallen into errors in his psychologically untenable attempt to conceive of “the number of temporal intuition, or the cardinal” as the second genetic level in the development of the number concept. The first level is supposed to be Represented [repräsentiert] through “the number of spatial intuition.” (W. Wundt, Philosophische Studien, V, Leipzig 1887, pp. 671ff.) From the possibility of continuing the successive positing of units arbitrarily far, Brix draws the highly precarious conclusion (Ibid., p. 675) that in such a way arbitrarily large numbers can be formed. But the mere succession of the repeated positings does not yet guarantee any synthesis, without which the collective unity of the number is inconceivable. It is precisely upon the inability actually to carry out such a synthesis, as we shall later discuss, that every attempt to form an authentic representation of the higher groups and numbers factually runs aground. Through the simplest of experiments Brix could have convinced himself that even nineteen positings of units are not clearly distinguishable from twenty, unless by the indirect means of symbolizations that serve as surrogates for syntheses actually carried out. But of course without the possibility of such distinction there can be no talk of an actual formation of the numbers concerned in terms of sequences of posited units.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Psychologie als Wissenschaft, Königsberg 1825, Part. II, p. 162.

    Google Scholar 

  4. System der Logik als Kunstlehre des Denkens, Berlin 1842, Part I, p. 279n.

    Google Scholar 

  5. I. Kant, Kritik der reinen Vernunft, Sämmtliche Werke, Hartenstein edition, Vol. III, Leipzig 1867, p. 144. B 180

    Google Scholar 

  6. Ibid, p. 142. B 179-180

    Google Scholar 

  7. A. Bain, Logic, 2nd ed., Part II, London 1873, p. 201f. Cp. the cogent critique of Bain’s theory in Chr. Sigwart, Logik, Vol. II, Freiburg i. Br. 1878, pp. 39ff.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Cf. H. Hankel, Vorlesungen über die complexen Zahlen und ihre Functionen, Part I, Leipzig 1867,p. 17.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Philosophische Aufsätze. Eduard Zeller zu seinem fünfzig-jährigen Doctor-Jubiläum gewidmet, Leipzig 1887.

    Google Scholar 

  10. See the Appendix to Part I of the present work.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Logische Studien, Iserlohn 1877, pp. 140f.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Ibid., p. 141.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Geschichte des Materialismus, Book II, 3rd edition, Iserlohn 1877, p. 26.

    Google Scholar 

  14. See the quotation on page 18 above.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Cp. the quotation following farther below.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Kritik der reinen Vernunft, B, §16 (Hartenstein ed., Vol. III, p. 117. B 134

    Google Scholar 

  17. Ibid., B, §15 (Hartenstein, p. 114). B 130

    Google Scholar 

  18. Cp., besides the above quotations, the Geschichte des Materialismus, Book II, 3rd Edition, pp. 119ff. In the Logischen Studien, pp 135f, he explains that we “at first” would have “in this expression [’synthesis’] little more than a formulation of the fact that in all our representations the unity of that which is manifold is present. …” But a few lines later the fact of synthesis is spoken of as a “process,” “through which we, as subject, first arise.”

    Google Scholar 

  19. Logische Studien, p. 148.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Ibid., p. 147.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Cp. C. Stumpf, Tonpsychologie, Vol. I, Leipzig 1883, pp. 105ff.

    Google Scholar 

  22. The mistakes here censured led Lange to strange results. The origin of the categories is supposed to lie in the representation of space. Its properties form the “norm for the functions of our understanding,” etc. “Thus,” Lange finally sums up (Ibid., p. 149), “the representation of space, along with its properties constitutive of our understanding, is revealed as the enduring and defining primitive form of our mental essence, as the true objective counterpart of our transcendental ego.” As soon as one tries to find a clear sense in these phrases, they disperse into nothingness.

    Google Scholar 

  23. J. J. Baumann, Die Lehre von Raum, Zeit und Mathematik in der neueren Philosophie, Berlin 1869, Vol. II, p. 571.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Ibid., p. 669

    Google Scholar 

  25. Ibid., P. 675.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Ibid., P. 671.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Ibid., p. 670.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Logische Studien, p. 140.

    Google Scholar 

  29. In: W. Wundt, Philos. Studien, Vol. V.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Ibid., pp. 671f.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Ibid., p. 672.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Among mathematicians, P. du Bois-Reymond may be mentioned here. In his Allgemeinen Functionentheorie, Part I, Tübingen 1882, p. 16, he comments that “Number is as it were what is left over in our soul when all that distinguished the things has evaporated and there is retained only the representation that the things were separate.” To be sure, being distinct in the sense of being separate is used here, which is no necessary element in a distinction theory of number. Moreover, du Bois-Reymond does not clearly hold to this idea of separateness; and he also seems to restrict himself to spatial objects.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Erkenntnistheoretische Logik, Bonn 1878, p. 405.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Ibid., p. 410.

    Google Scholar 

  35. The Principles of Science, 2nd Edition, London 1883, p. 156.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Ibid., pp. 158 and 159.

    Google Scholar 

  37. This also is probably connected with the fact that from time to time, especially in the case of physical contents, one uses “being distinct” as synonymous with “being separate” (in intuition), expressions which do not always coincide, as is to be seen from the relation of whole and part. We therefore do not take this to be an essentially new kind of equivocation.

    Google Scholar 

  38. We will call them “primary relations.” The further details on the division here indicated, which will prove to be important for purposes of a characterization of the collective combination, are given in Chapter III.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Chr. Sigwart, Logik, Vol. II, p. 37.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Cp. the quotation above.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Logik, Vol. II, pp. 38f.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Logik, Vol. II, p. 37.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Ibid., p. 38.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Ibid., p. 41.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Ibid., p. 43.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Ibid., p. 36.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Logik, Vol. I, p. 36

    Google Scholar 

  48. Ibid., p. 279n. “The opinion that it is first through distinguishing that a representation becomes determinate forgets that the distinguishing itself is only possible between different representations already present, and that the distinction therefore does not produce the different contents.” Here Sigwart is referring to H. Ulrici, Compendium der Logik, 2nd Edition, Leipzig 1872, p. 60.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Very appropriately, therefore, in his Tonpsychologie (Vol. I, p. 96) Stumpf defines analysis as the noting of a plurality.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Errors with regard to the function of distinguishing in the representation of several objects are so easy to fall into that we are not surprised to find them already present in older writers. Cf. J. Locke, An Essay, Book II, ch. XI, sect. 1, and Book IV, ch. I, sect. 4, and ch. VII, sect. 4, and elsewhere. Further, James Mill, Analysis of the Phenomena of the Human Mind, ed. by J. St. Mill, Vol. II, London 1879, p. 15: “As having a sensation, and a sensation, and knowing them, that is, distinguishing them, are the same thing;.…” He also repeats this assertion many times elsewhere.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2003 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Husserl, E. (2003). Critical Developments. In: Philosophy of Arithmetic. Edmund Husserl, vol 10. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-0060-4_3

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-0060-4_3

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-1-4020-1603-5

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-010-0060-4

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics