Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Episteme ((EPIS,volume 7))

  • 256 Accesses

Abstract

In the context of 19th-century physics, geometry was quite naturally interpreted as the science of space, space itself being conceived as a self-subsisting entity, no less real than the spatial things moving across it. Paradoxically, however, the propositions of this science did not seem to be liable to empirical corroboration or refutation. Since the times of the Greeks, no geometer had ever thought of subjecting his conclusions to the verdict of experiment. And philosophers, from Plato to Kant, viewed geometry as the one unquestionable instance of non-trivial a priori knowledge, i.e. knowledge relevant to things that exist, yet not dependent on our experience of them. Even such an extreme empiricist as Hume regarded geometry as a non-empirical science, concerned not with matters of fact, but with relations of ideas. The discovery of non-Euclidean geometries shattered the unanimity of philosophers on this point. The existence of a variety of equally consistent systems of geometry was immediately thought to lend support to a different view of this science. The established Euclidean system could now be regarded as a physical theory, highly corroborated by experience, but liable to be eventually proved inexact. We have seen that Gauss and Lobachevsky, Riemann and Helmholtz took this empiricist view of geometry.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

4.1 Empiricism in Geometry

  1. Gauss, WW, Vol.8, p. 177. Quoted above, p.55.

    Google Scholar 

  2. J.S. Mill, SL, pp.209–261, 607–621; cf. Early Draft of the Logic, ibid, pp.1083–1097. That the first principles of arithmetic are generalizations from experience is stated on p.257. Arithmetic, however, differs from geometry in so far as the former “is deduced wholly from propositions exactly true”, while the latter partly depends, as we shall see, on “hypotheses or assumptions which are only approximations to the truth”. (J.S. Mill, SL, p. 1092; cf. pp.258f.).

    Google Scholar 

  3. J.S. Mill, SL, p.218.

    Google Scholar 

  4. J.S. Mill, SL, p. 1088.

    Google Scholar 

  5. J.S. Mill, SL, p.618n. I imagine that he expects them to be coplanar as well.

    Google Scholar 

  6. J.S. Mill, SL, p.225.

    Google Scholar 

  7. J.S. Mill, SL, p.225. “Inconceivable” for Mill is apparently everything that we would repute unimaginable.

    Google Scholar 

  8. J.S. Mill, SL, p.225.

    Google Scholar 

  9. J.S. Mill, SL, p.227n. (The note from which our quotation is taken was added by Mill in 1872.)

    Google Scholar 

  10. J.S. Mill, SL, pp.228f. In the first three editions the text enclosed by the asterisks read as follows: “suppressing some of those which it has”.

    Google Scholar 

  11. J.S. Mill, SL, p.230.

    Google Scholar 

  12. J.S. Mill, SL, pp.229f. The reader will not fail to observe that the last of the two axioms is incompatible with BL geometry while the first excludes spherical geometry. That Mill, who apparently knew nothing of the new developments in mathematics, should have chosen precisely such examples shows to what extent the subject was in the air at that time.

    Google Scholar 

  13. J.S. Mill, SL, p. 1089.

    Google Scholar 

  14. J.S. Mill, SL, p.232n. (note added in 1865; my italics).

    Google Scholar 

  15. J.S. Mill, SL, p.233.

    Google Scholar 

  16. J.S. Mill, SL, p.234.

    Google Scholar 

  17. J.S. Mill, SL, p.235.

    Google Scholar 

  18. J.S. Mill, SL, pp.115f.

    Google Scholar 

  19. J.S. Mill, SL, p. 1089.

    Google Scholar 

  20. J.S. Mill, SL, p.259.

    Google Scholar 

  21. J.S. Mill, SL, p.616 (text of the first four editions).

    Google Scholar 

  22. J.S. Mill, SL, pp.616f.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Ueberweg, PG, p.314.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Ueberweg, PG, pp.312f.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Ueberweg, PG, p.268.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Ueberweg, PG, p.315.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Ueberweg, PG, p.269.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Ueberweg, PG, pp.269f.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Ueberweg, PG, p.313.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Theorem 25 (Ueberweg, PG, p.287). The ‘proof’ of the theorem involves many tacit assumptions, whereby, among other things, elliptic and spherical geometry are implicitly excluded.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Ueberweg, PG, p.291.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Theorem 47 (Ueberweg, PG, p.304).

    Google Scholar 

  33. Theorem 49b (Ibid., p.305).

    Google Scholar 

  34. Erdmann, AG, p.38. In the same year, 1877, in which Erdmann’s book was published, Georg Cantor discovered that the above expression of dimension number is inadequate, because Rn can be mapped bijectively onto R. See Cantor, GA, pp.119–133. Cantor’s proof is sketched in Kline, MT, pp.997f.

    Google Scholar 

  35. “Die Teilbarkeit ins unendliche, die jeder Raumanschauung anhaftet” (Erdmann, AG, p.38). This is, of course, highly questionable as a description of spatial perception. We must assume that Erdmann, like most empiricist philosophers, allows the bounty of imagination to make up for the stinginess of the senses.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Erdmann, AG, p.39. The alleged intuitive fact of infinite divisibility does not warrant the empjpyment of such strong analytical means for expressing it. It would suffice to let the coordinates take all rational values between their value at A and their value at B, or merely all values expressible by means of a terminating decimal fraction.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Erdmann, AG, p.40.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Erdmann, AG, pp.58f.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Erdmann, AG, pp.93f.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Erdmann, AG, p. 116.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Erdmann, AG, p. 146.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Cf. Erdmann, AG, pp.59ff., 91, 141ff.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Erdmann, AG, p.91; cf. pp.115, 135, 145, 152f. On Heimholtz, see Section 3.1.3.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Erdmann, AG, pp.144f. Erdmann refers to the dimension number of space on pp.38, 49, 83, 95, 143; nowhere do I find an argument for the above quoted statement.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Erdmann, AG, pp.H8f.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Erdmann, AG, pp.94f.; cf. p. 128.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Erdmann, AG, pp.157.; cf. p.44n.2, p.50.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Erdmann, AG, p.158; (my italics). Cf. Heimholtz (1866), p.197; quoted above, p.167, Section 3.1.3.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Erdmann, AG, p. 159. I take it that the geometric concepts of construction (die geometrische Constructionsbegriffe) are concepts such as straight line and circle, which enter into the description of geometrical constructions.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Erdmann, AG, p. 159.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Erdmann, AG, p. 160.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Erdmann, AG, p. 161.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Erdmann, AG, p. 169.

    Google Scholar 

  54. Erdmann, AG, p. 170.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Erdmann, AG, p. 170. Erdmann admits here that experimental results may show that space curvature is not constant. According to the Helmholtzian stance taken by Erdmann in the rest of the book, such experimental discovery would imply that the ideal of a perfectly rigid motion cannot be indefinitely approached, and that, as a consequence of this, there is an upper bound to the accuracy of actual geometrical measurements.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Calinon (1891), p.375.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Calinon (1891), p.375.

    Google Scholar 

  58. Calinon (1889), p.589. Cf. Calinon (1891), p.368; “La Géométrie générale est l’étude de tous les groupes de formes dont les définitions premières sont astreintes à une condition unique, qui est de ne donner lieu à aucune contradiction, lorsqu’on les soumet au raisonnement géométrique indéfiniment prolongé”.

    Google Scholar 

  59. Calinon (1891), p.375. Cf. Klein (1890), p.571, quoted above, p.149, Section 2.3.10.

    Google Scholar 

  60. Calinon (1891), p.375.

    Google Scholar 

  61. Calinon (1889), p.590. Calinon’s “general geometry” embraces Euclidean geometry, BL geometry and the so-called geometry of Riemann, that is, spherical or elliptic geometry. It is, in other words, a theory of maximally symmetric spaces (p. 184). The name “general geometry” indicates that Calinon was less open-minded than he thought.

    Google Scholar 

  62. Calinon (1891), pp.368f. Identical spaces, in this sense, were called isogenous (isogènes) by Delboeuf, a term often used in the French literature of this period. See pp.206f.

    Google Scholar 

  63. Calinon (1889), p.594.

    Google Scholar 

  64. Calinon (1889), p.595.

    Google Scholar 

  65. Calinon (1891), p.374 (my italics).

    Google Scholar 

  66. Calinon (1893), p.605. The paper of 1893 is written in what the author calls an “idealistic” language; that is, space is identified there with our perceptually based representation of space. Calinon says that his views on the matters discussed by him can also be set forth in a realistic language, a task which he proposes as an exercise to the reader. In a realistic version of Calinon’s paper we ought perhaps to ascribe a definite though unknown geometric structure to physical space. But it seems clear that in Calinon’s opinion it makes no scientific sense to state hypotheses about such a structure. The choice of a geometry in physics must be made in the light of the requirements of the problem at hand, not with a view to determining the essence of things in themselves.

    Google Scholar 

  67. Published in the Revue générale des sciences on December 15, 1891. See Part 4.4.

    Google Scholar 

  68. Calinon (1893), p.607. Such are also the criteria usually applied when choosing a coordinate system. It is amazing that the great mathematician Poincaré should have overlooked this side of the analogy drawn by him.

    Google Scholar 

  69. Calinon (1893), p.607.

    Google Scholar 

  70. Mach, EI, pp.337–448. The two longest chapters (pp.353–422) had previously been published in English in The Monist. See References.

    Google Scholar 

  71. H. Poincaré, “Le continu mathématique” (1893); “L’espace et la géométrie” (1895); “On the foundations of geometry” (1898). See Part 4.4. Federico Enriques published, shortly before Mach, a study explaining the psychological development of geometry from an empiricist point of view. (Enriques, “Sulla spiegazione psicologica dei postulati della geometria” (1901).) I do not think it would be rewarding to discuss Enriques’ views here. They are readily accessible in English in Enriques, PS, pp. 199–231.

    Google Scholar 

  72. Mach, EI, p.389; cf. pp.371, 381.

    Google Scholar 

  73. Mach, EI, p.337. Compare Mach’s illuminating description of time-sensations in EI, p.423.

    Google Scholar 

  74. Mach, EI, p.345.

    Google Scholar 

  75. Mach distinguished the geometrical and the physiological properties of a figure in space in his Beiträge zur Analyse der Empfindungen (1886), pp.44, 54, long before Poincaré introduced the concepts of espace géométrique and espace représentatif in “L’espace et la géométrie” (1895).

    Google Scholar 

  76. Mach, El, p.337.

    Google Scholar 

  77. Mach, El, p.339.

    Google Scholar 

  78. Mach, EI. p.340.

    Google Scholar 

  79. Mach, EI, p.347. I fail to see how the experiences described by Mach might justify the conclusion that space is infinite, and not just unlimited. This is one of those wild speculative jumps that empiricists must make every now and then to reconcile their philosophy with experience.

    Google Scholar 

  80. Mach, EI, p.355. The reader will probably notice that in order to transport a body from a neighbourhood FGH to a neighbourhood MNO, as required by the experiment described above, we must regard it as located in the unitary objective physical space whose very idea supposedly arises out of such experiments.

    Google Scholar 

  81. Mach, EI, p.434.

    Google Scholar 

  82. Mach, EI, p.367.

    Google Scholar 

  83. Mach, EI, p.380.

    Google Scholar 

  84. Mach, EI, p.367.

    Google Scholar 

  85. Mach, EI, p.368.

    Google Scholar 

  86. Mach, EI, pp.368f.

    Google Scholar 

  87. Mach, EI, p.380. The last remark, in fact, agrees with the opinion of authors such as Klein and Enriques, who emphasized the optical origin of our idea of straightness, for they saw in visual intuition the root of projective, not of metric geometry (see above, Section 2.3.10, p. 147; Enriques, PS, pp.205ff.).

    Google Scholar 

  88. Mach, EI, p.370.

    Google Scholar 

  89. Mach, EI, p.371.

    Google Scholar 

  90. Mach, EI, p.385.

    Google Scholar 

  91. Mach, EI, p.409.

    Google Scholar 

  92. Mach, EI, p.414.

    Google Scholar 

  93. Mach, EI, p.418.

    Google Scholar 

  94. Mach, EI, p.418.

    Google Scholar 

4.2 The Uproar of Boeotians

  1. Krause, loc. cit., p.84; quoted by Schlick in Helmholtz, SE, p.29, n.25.

    Google Scholar 

  2. “Nur ein einziger grosser und zusammenhängender Irrtum”. Lotze, M, p.234.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Lotze rejects Kant’s arguments for the “transcendental ideality” of space, but supports it with another argument of his own: space as an aggregate of equal points can only be held together by consciousness. (Lotze, M, pp.211f.)

    Google Scholar 

  4. Lotze, M, p.223.

    Google Scholar 

  5. “Eines Ordnungssystems leerer Plätze”. (Lotze, M, p.235).

    Google Scholar 

  6. Lotze, M, pp.241f.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Lotze, M, p.247. I have changed Lotze’s lettering to make the meaning clearer.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Wundt, L, Vol.I, pp.478–506; Vol.II, pp. 176–208. I quote Vol.1 after the fifth (posthumous) edition of 1924.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Wundt, L, Vol.I, p.489: “Die unmittelbare gegebene Ordnung unserer Wahrnehmungsinhalte.” Ibid., p.504: “Eine Ordnung von Empfindungen”.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Wundt, L, Vol.I, p.497.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Wundt, L, Vol.I, p.501.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Wundt, L, Vol.I, p.503.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Wundt, L, Vol.I, p.504.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Wundt, L, Vol.I, p.494.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Wundt, L, Vol.I, p.483.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Wundt, L, Vol.I, p.485.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Wundt, L, Vol.I, p.482.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Wundt, L, Vol.I, p.492. “Self-congruence” means that a figure congruent with a given figure can be constructed anywhere in space. I have quoted Wundt’s shortened definition in the second paragraph of p.492. In the first paragraph we find a more explicit definition. In it, instead of unendlich (infinite), Wundt writes unbegrenzt (unlimited). This longer definition is therefore compatible with spherical and elliptic geometry; it also covers all the hypersurfaces of elliptic and hyperbolic 4-space which are isometric to Euclidean 3-space, etc.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Kant, Ak., II, pp.404f. (quoted on p.31).

    Google Scholar 

  20. Wundt, L, I, p.488.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Wundt, L, I, p.488.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Wundt, L, I, p.484.

    Google Scholar 

  23. First published in Renouvier’s Critique philosophique in November 1889, as a reply to Léchalas’ paper on general geometry, published in the same journal in September 1889 (see ibid., p.337n.). I quote from Renouvier (1891), a considerably revised and enlarged version published in Pillon’s Année philosophique.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Renouvier (1891), p.3.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Renouvier (1891), p.64.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Renouvier (1891), p.43.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Renouvier (1891), p.4.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Renouvier (1891), p.4.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Renouvier (1891), p.20. (My paraphrase.)

    Google Scholar 

  30. “La ruine entière de l’idéation géométrique”. (Renouvier (1891), p.45.)

    Google Scholar 

  31. Renouvier (1891), p.45.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Renouvier (1891), p.66.

    Google Scholar 

  33. See pp. 153 and 206.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Delboeuf, PPG, p.67.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Delboeuf, PPG, p. 129.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Delboeuf, PPG, p.50.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Delboeuf, ANG, I, p.456. Delboeuf concludes: “L’espace géométrique ou euclidien est donc un espace imaginaire, un espace hypothétique, n’ayant de commun avec la réalité que ceci qu’elle en a fourni l’idée, parce que les solides ont l’air de s’y transporter sans altération sensible.” (Ibid., pp.464f.) As we know, this empirical fact which according to Delboeuf “provides the idea of Euclidean space” fits equally well with every space of constant curvature.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Delboeuf, ANG, II, p.372.

    Google Scholar 

4.3 Russell’s Apriorism of 1897

  1. Russell, FG, New York: Dover, 1956.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Russell, FG, p.136.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Kant, KrV, B 40.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Kant, KrV, B 246. This is one of the many passages where Kant might seem to favour a psychological conception of the a priori.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Russell, FG, p.28.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Russell, FG, p. 118.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Russell, FG, p. 132.

    Google Scholar 

  8. The reader is advised to read the argument in Russell, FG, pp. 136f.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Russell, FG, pp.139f. Russell’s rejection of infinite-dimensional spaces is not an instance of mathematical ignorance — such spaces had not yet been discovered — but of a typically unmathematical narrow-mindedness which often crops up in philosophical literature.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Russell, FG, p. 149.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Russell, FG, p.46.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Russell, FG, p. 118.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Russell, FG, p. 147.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Russell, FG, p. 119; cf. p.30.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Russell, FG, p.35.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Russell, FG, p. 164.

    Google Scholar 

  17. See above, p. 124, Section 2.3.5.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Russell, FG, p. 161.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Russell, FG, p. 163. Riemann had made the same remark; see above, Section 2.2.9, p. 104.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Russell, FG, p. 164.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Russell, FG, p. 164.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Russell, FG, p. 150.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Russell, FG, pp.78, 79.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Russell, FG, p.79.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Russell, FG, p.81.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Russell, FG, p. 152.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Erdmann, AG, p.60.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Russell, FG, p. 155.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Russell, FG, pp.153f. The deduction of the axiom of free mobility from the relativity of position in Russell, FG, p. 160, begs the question. Relativity of position implies that the form of externality is homogeneous, says Russell, and free mobility follows from homogeneity “for our form would not be homogeneous unless it allowed, in every part, shapes or systems of relations, which it allowed in any other part” (Ibid.). This argument makes sense only if metrically determined shapes have been defined in our form of externality.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Couturat (1898), p.373f.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Russell (1898), p.763.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Russell, FG, pp.158f.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Russell (1898), p.760. Russell says that the experiment was suggested to him by A.N. Whitehead.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Russell, FG, p.74.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Russell (1899), pp.703–707.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Russell, “L’idée d’ordre et la position absolue dans l’espace et le temps” (1900). Russell (1901) is the corrected and slightly expanded English version of this paper.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Russell, Principles, p.372.

    Google Scholar 

4.4 Henri Poincaré

  1. Poincaré (1898b), now in Poincaré, VS, Chapter II, especially pp.47–54.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Neumann, PGNT, p. 18.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Lange (1885), p.338 (my paraphrase). These so-called theorems are of course postulates. Lange’s “proof” of the first is really a consistency proof: given an inertial system relatively to which a particle moves in a straight line, one cannot construct a second inertial system relatively to which that same particle does not move in a straight line.

    Google Scholar 

  4. The most complete study of Poincaré’s philosophy of geometry is still Rougier, La philosophie géométrique de Henri Poincaré (1920).

    Google Scholar 

  5. The book by Mooij, La philosophie des mathématiques de Henri Poincaré (1966) devotes to it only a short rather unilluminating chapter (pp.3–29). A penetrating analysis of its foundations is given in Vuillemin (1972).

    Google Scholar 

  6. “There can be little doubt that any deductive theory is capable of translation into a ‘contrary’ deductive theory.” (Black (1942), p.345). Black does not say “into any contrary theory”, but, as we shall see, his thesis on the translatability of axiomatic theories does not lend support to geometrical conventionalism unless we understand it in this strong sense.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Black (1942), pp.341f.

    Google Scholar 

  8. See Tarski, LSM, p.306; also pp.243, 248, Section 3.2.9.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Poincaré (1891), p.774; reprinted in SH, p.77.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Kant, KrV, B146, A557/B585, A613f./B641f.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Poincaré, SH, Chapter V, “L’expérience et le géométrie”, a chapter composed of passages pieced together from Poincaré (1891), (1899), (1900), plus a short summary of some of the ideas presented in Poincaré (1898).

    Google Scholar 

  12. See Section 4.4.5.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Poincaré, SH, p.76; Poincaré (1898), pp.42f. See below, pp.351f., Section 4.4.5.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Poincaré, SH, p. 101; cf. pp.75, 95.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Poincaré, SH, p.99. Compare Einstein’s formulation of the general principle of relativity: “Natural laws are only statements about spatio-temporal coincidences; therefore their natural expression must consist in generally covariant equations”. (Einstein (1918), p.241.)

    Google Scholar 

  16. Minkowski (1908). In fact, Minkowski’s contribution concerned only the underlying manifold of special relativity, which he showed to be a semi-Riemannian 4-manifold (see Appendix, p.372). But he paved the way for the four-dimensional formulation of Newtonian mechanics by Cartan (1923, 1924).

    Google Scholar 

  17. Poincaré (1891), p.774; SH, pp.95f. (my italics). On “Riemann’s geometry” see Part 2.2, Note 52.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Poincaré foresaw the rise of “an entirely new mechanics chiefly characterized by the fact that no velocity can surpass that of light”. (Poincaré, VS, pp.138f.; the passage belongs to a lecture given in St. Louis in 1904.)

    Google Scholar 

  19. Poincaré, SH, p. 103.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Poincaré, Oeuvres, Vol.XI, p.90.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Poincaré, Oeuvres, Vol.XI, p.91.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Poincaré, Oeuvres, Vol.XI, p.91. The “operations” of the group are not what we would call thus (namely, the group product and the mapping which assigns to every element its own inverse), but simply the elements of the group; the group is viewed as “operating” through them on an underlying space.

    Google Scholar 

  23. See however Glymour (1972).

    Google Scholar 

  24. Poincaré (1898), (1903). See below, Section 4.4.5.

    Google Scholar 

  25. See pp.172f., where this is explained in connection with Lie groups.

    Google Scholar 

  26. Poincaré (1898), p.40. Lie’s concept of a Zahlenmannigfaltigkeit is discussed in Part 3.1, Note 42.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Poincaré (1900), p.81.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Poincaré (1900), p.85; SH, p.104.

    Google Scholar 

  29. A valuable recent exception is Vuillemin (1972).

    Google Scholar 

  30. Poincaré, SH, p.51.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Poincaré (1898), p. 1.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Poincaré, VS, pp.73f.; (1898), p.2.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Poincaré, (1898), p.3.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Instead of cancels, Poincaré says corrects. Instead of locomotion he says displacement. See Note 55.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Poincaré, SH, p.51.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Poincaré (1898), pp.14f. Poincaré’s argument implies that every displacement is joined to 0 by a simple physical continuum; it follows easily that any two displacements are also joined thus.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Poincaré (1898), p.23. On the form and material of a group, see above, pp.336f.

    Google Scholar 

  38. They will be found in Poincaré (1898), pp.23–32 and in a much improved version in Poincaré, VS, pp.80–93.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Poincaré (1898), p.5; cf. Poincaré (1895), now in SH, p.82. By drawing our attention to the fact that Euclidean space is not a whit more imaginable than the non-Euclidean spaces Poincaré has finally disposed of a staple Boeotian argument.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Poincaré (1898), p.42.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Poincaré, SH, p.76.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Poincaré (1898), p.42.

    Google Scholar 

  43. His main contribution is contained in his long paper “Analysis situs” (1895) and its five supplements, published between 1899 and 1904. But the “qualitative theory” of differential equations developed in his four papers “Sur les courbes définies par une équation différentielle” (1881–1886) also follows an essentially topological approach. See Kline, MT, pp.732ff., 1170ff.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Poincaré, VS, pp.59f.; DP, pp.132ff.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Poincaré, DP, p. 134. We say, today, that two figures F, G (belonging to the same or to different topological spaces) are topologically equivalent if there is a continuous bijection f: F → G whose inverse f -1 is also continuous. This concept is wider than the one proposed by Poincaré in DP. It should be noted, however, that the name homeomorphism given today to such bijections as f was introduced by Poincaré. See Georg Feigl (1928), p.274.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Poincaré, VS, p.59; cf. VS, p.55; FS, p.417; DP, pp.100, 136.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Poincaré, DP, p. 135; VS, p.60.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Poincaré (1893); reprinted in Poincaré, SH, pp.58–60.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Euclid, Book I, Definitions 3 and 6; Book XI, Definition 2. (Heath, EE, Vol.I, pp.165, 171; vol.III, p.263.) Compare Menger (1926), pp.118f.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Poincaré, SH, pp.58–60; VS, pp.61–64.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Poincaré, SH, p.60; VS, pp.64f.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1984 D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, Holland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Torretti, R. (1984). Empiricism, Apriorism, Conventionalism. In: Philosophy of Geometry from Riemann to Poincaré. Episteme, vol 7. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-9909-1_4

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-9909-1_4

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-277-1837-2

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-009-9909-1

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics