Skip to main content

Toward a Broader Empiricism

  • Chapter
The Philosophy of John Dewey
  • 156 Accesses

Abstract

There is a felt need for reunion in philosophy, for new perspective and vision that is informed by the lessons of careful analysis. In this search for new directions, there is much to be learned from John Dewey, who sought to unite speculative imagination with a sensitive concern for the variety of human experience and the specific “problems of men.”1

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Richard J. Bernstein, “Introduction,” On Experience, Nature, and Freedom, ed. Richard J. Bernstein (New York: Liberal Arts Press, 1960), p. xlvii.

    Google Scholar 

  2. “The Experimental Theory of Knowledge,” in Influence of Darwin, p. 77. Lest the passage be thought unrepresentative, see also “Experience, Knowledge, and Value: A Rejoinder.” pp. 561, 566–567 and Dewey’s remarks about defining knowledge “in the honorific sense” in “Propositions, Warranted Assertibility, and Truth,” in Problems of Men, pp. 332, 340.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Above, p. 11.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Above, p. 25.

    Google Scholar 

  5. Above, p. 92.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Above, p. 109.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Logic, p. 127.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Reconstruction in Philosophy, enl. ed., p. 96.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Ibid.,p. 118.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Experience and Nature, 2d ed., p. 308.

    Google Scholar 

  11. “Philosophies of Freedom,” in Philosophy and Civilization, p. 295.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Logic, pp. 104–105. The original text is italicized.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Experience and Nature, 2d ed., p. 331.

    Google Scholar 

  14. “Experience, Knowledge, and Value: A Rejoinder,” pp. 561, 567–568.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Logic, p. 104.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Reconstruction in Philosophy, enl. ed., passim, esp. Introduction, Chs. IV and V; Quest for Certainty, passim, esp. pp. 72–73, 290–291.

    Google Scholar 

  17. See, e.g., “The Need for a Recovery of Philosophy,” in Creative Intelligence: “The Development of American Pragmatism,” in Philosophy and Civilization; Reconstruction in Philosophy, enl. ed., Chs. IV and V. Andrew J. Reck has commented in a review of this manuscript that Dewey’s category of continuity can be used to save Dewey’s method from the criticism that it attends to consequences but neglects antecedents. Reck also cites John Herman Randall, Jr., as having employed the category of continuity in his Nature and Historical Experience (New York: Columbia University Press, 1958) to avoid this problem. In response to these points, Reck’s suggestion is reasonable but I still find that the difficulty remains in Dewey’s philosophy. For example, in Dewey’s mature work, Logic: The Theory of Inquiry, he employs the category of continuity primarily to emphasize the links between lower (less complex) and higher (more complex) forms of nature and activities. (See e.g., pp. 19, 23, 35–36.) Later in the Logic, Dewey does discuss retrospective and prospective reference in connection with his theory of causal propositions and the sharp dichotomy I have noted between antecedents and consequences appears again. (See pp. 461–462; other instances of the dichotomy can be found in this same work, pp. 131, 499, 511–512.) Randall’s metaphysics, on the other hand, may very well avoid this difficulty. Insofar as Randall’s views represent a modification of Dewey’s, his success is further testimony to my general thesis that much of Dewey’s thought can be reconciled with that of his critics.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1977 Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague, Netherlands

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Dewey, R.E. (1977). Toward a Broader Empiricism. In: The Philosophy of John Dewey. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-9666-3_8

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-9666-3_8

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-247-1980-8

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-009-9666-3

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics