Advertisement

Self-Profile

  • Keith Lehrer
Part of the Profiles book series (PROF, volume 2)

Abstract

My study of philosophy began at the University of Minnesota in 1953. My first course was taught by a graduate student, Juarez Paz, who has subsequently become a distinguished academic in his native country, Guatemala. I remember very distinctly what question it was that sparked my curiosity and settled my choice of career. We were reading Candide by Voltaire. Juarez Paz, who was studying emotivism in preparation for his dissertation, suggested that when Pangloss described the horrors of the world and said, “This is the best of all possible worlds’, what Pangloss said added nothing further to his description of world. Pangloss is making no further claim about the world when he says that it is best, or the best possible, he is, Juarez Paz suggested, expressing his approval of the world. Most members of the class thought that this opinion was perverse, that Pangloss was making an important, and false, claim about the world. I was convinced that his words added nothing whatever to his description of the world. I was sure I had a fundamental insight into morality and avidly defended the idea in subsequent classroom discussions. Whatever the merits of the idea, I was enraptured. Philosophy had got her bite on me, and though I feigned uncertainty, my choice of career was settled from that moment.

Keywords

Common Sense Social Choice Probability Assignment Epistemic Justification False Proposition 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Anscombe, G. E. M.: ‘Soft Determinism’, in Contemporary Aspects of Philosophy (ed. by G. Ryle) (Oriel Press, London, 1976 ), pp. 148–160.Google Scholar
  2. Arrow, K.: Social Choice and Individual Values (John Wiley and Sons. New York, 1951, second edition, 1963 ).Google Scholar
  3. Aune, B.: ‘Hypothetical and “Can”: Another Look’, Analysis 27 (1967). 191–195.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Carnap, R.: The Logical Foundations of Probability ( University of Chicago, Chicago, 1962 ).Google Scholar
  5. Carter, R.: ‘Lehrer’s Fourth Condition for Knowing’. Philosophical Studies 31 (1977), 327–336.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Chisholm, R. M.: Perceiving: A Philosophical Study ( Cornell University. Ithaca. 1957 ).Google Scholar
  7. Chisholm, R. M.: Theory of Knowledge ( Second edition. Prentice-Hall. Englewood Cliffs, 1977 ).Google Scholar
  8. Frankfurt, H.: ‘Freedom of the Will and the Concept of a Person’, Journal of Philosophy 68 (1971), 5–20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Gettier, E. L.: ‘Is Justified True Belief Knowledge?’. Analysis 23 (1963). 121–123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Goldman, A. I.: ‘A Causal Theory of Knowing’. Journal of Philosophy 64 (1967), 355–372.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Harman, G.: Thought (Princeton University Press.,Princeton. 1973).Google Scholar
  12. Hempel, C. G.: ‘Deductive-Nomological vs Statistical Explanation’, in Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science Vol. III(ed. by H. Feigl and G. Maxwell) ( University of Minnesota, Minneapolis. 1962 ). pp. 98–169.Google Scholar
  13. Hilpinen, R.: ‘Rules of Acceptance and Inductive Logic’. Acta Philosophica Fennica 22 (1968).Google Scholar
  14. Hilpinen. R.: ‘Knowledge and Justification’, Ajatus 33 (1971). 7–39.Google Scholar
  15. Hintikka. J.; ‘A Two-Dimensional Continuum of Inductive Methods’, in Aspects of Inductive Logic (ed. by J. Hintikka and P. Suppes) (North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1966 ), pp. 113–132.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Hintikka, J. and Pietarinen, J.: ‘Semantic Information and Inductive Logic’, in Aspects of Inductive Logic (ed. by J. Hintikka and P. Suppes) (North-Holland, Amsterdam, 1966 ), pp. 96–112.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Horgan, T.: ‘Lehreron “Could” Statements’ Philosophical Studies 32 (1977), 403–411.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Jeffrey. R. C.: The Logic of Decision ( McGraw-Hill. New York, 1965 ).Google Scholar
  19. Jeffrey, R. C.: ‘Preferences Among Preferences’, Journal of Philosophy 71 (1974), 377–391.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Klein, P. D.: ‘A Proposed Definition of Propositional Knowledge’, Journal of Philosophy 68 (1971), 471–482.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Kyburg, H.: The Logical Foundations of Statistical Inference ( Reidel, Dordrecht, 1974 ).Google Scholar
  22. Levi, I.: Gambling with Truth ( Random House, New York, 1967 ).Google Scholar
  23. Levi, I.: ‘Truth, Content, and Ties’, Journal of Philosophy 68 (1971), 865–876.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Pastin, M.: ‘Critical Review of Keith Lehrer’s Knowledge’, Nous 11 (1977), 431–437.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Paxson, T. D.: ‘A New Subjectivist Theory of Knowledge: A Critical Discussion’, Grazer Philosophische Studien 1 (1975), 193–199.Google Scholar
  26. Pollock. J.: Subjunctive Reasoning ( Reidel, Dordrecht, 1976 ).Google Scholar
  27. Ramsey, F. P.: ‘Truth and Probability’, in The Foundations of Mathematics (ed. by R. Braithwaite) (Routledge and Kegan Paul, London, 1950 ), pp. 156–198.Google Scholar
  28. Reichenbach, H.: The Theory of Probability ( University of California, Berkeley and Los Angeles, 1949 ).Google Scholar
  29. Savage, L. J.: Foundations of Statistics ( John Wiley and Sons, New York, 1954 ).Google Scholar
  30. Sellars, W.: ‘Induction as Vindication’, Philosophy of Science 31 (1964).Google Scholar
  31. Wagner. C.: ‘Consensus Through Respect: A Model of Rational Group Decision-Making’, Philosophical Studies 34 (1978), 335–349.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, Holland 1980

Authors and Affiliations

  • Keith Lehrer

There are no affiliations available

Personalised recommendations