Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Phaenomenologica ((PHAE,volume 93))

  • 90 Accesses

Abstract

Our undertaking does not require even a nearly complete account of Kant’s ethics, and indeed it would not be expedient to give one. We need only to present Kant’s chief views as clearly as we can, so that we shall have a groundwork for the critique to follow; anything merely secondary may be disregarded.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals, p. 445. (Translators note: For translations of passages from the Groundwork and the Critique of Practical Reason, I have relied on H.J. Paton (New York, 1964) and L. W. Beck (New York, 1956) respectively. In some places I depart from their translations without remark. Page references to these and other works by Kant are to the Akademie - Ausgabe. The pagination of this edition is also given by Paton and Beck. - A small t, b, or m after a page number refers the reader to the top, bottom, or middle of the page.)

    Google Scholar 

  2. Ibid., p. 394; cf. pp. 399 b., 400 t., and 435 m.

    Google Scholar 

  3. Ibid, p. 394.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Ibid., pp. 394, 397–401, 403 f., 407, 415, 426 ff., 435 f., 439, 449 f., and 454; no fewer

    Google Scholar 

  5. Groundwork, p. 393.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Critique of Practical Reason, pp. 21 f.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Ibid., pp. 32 and 81; The Metaphysics of Morals, p. 379.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Critique of Pure Reason, B 263.

    Google Scholar 

  9. Critique of Practical Reason, p. 19.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Groundwork, p. 424.

    Google Scholar 

  11. Ibid., p. 412. For a similar definition see p. 427.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Critique of Practical Reason, p. 119 b. and Critique of Pure Reason, A 405, B 356.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Groundwork, p. 414.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Critique of Practical Reason, p. 30. Cf. Groundwork, p. 421.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Groundwork, p. 423.

    Google Scholar 

  16. The widespread view that the categorical imperative only prohibits is thus a misconcep-tion, like the view that it is without any content

    Google Scholar 

  17. Ibid., p. 416. Cf. p. 435 m. and Critique of Practical Reason, pp. 71 m., 116, and 147.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Ibid., p. 441. Cf. Critique of Practical Reason, p. 34.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Critique of Practical Reason, p. 34.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Groundwork, p. 436 ff. Cf. Critique of Practical Reason, pp. 56 ff. and 67 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Ibid., p. 429.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Ibid., pp. 429t. and 431.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Ibid., pp. 437–8.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Critique of Practical Reason, pp. 71 b. and 81 m.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Groundwork, p. 4601.; Critique of Practical Reason, pp. 75 and 80; The Metaphysics of Morals, pp. 390/400.

    Google Scholar 

  26. The Metaphysics of Morals, Introduction.

    Google Scholar 

  27. Critique of Practical Reason, pp. 38–40.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Groundwork, p. 401 n.

    Google Scholar 

  29. This follows mediately, but especially clearly, from the Critique of Practical Reason, p. 23 n. 1.

    Google Scholar 

  30. Ibid., p. 76.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Most of them are on pp. 397–399.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Groundwork, p. 398.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Compare Schiller’s witty distich in “Die Philosophen”: “Gerne dien ich den Freunden, doch tu ich es leider mit Neigung,/ Und so wurmt es mir oft, daβ ich nicht tugendhaft bin”. “Always glad to help a friend, yet sadly I am so inclined,/ And so this often vexes me, not being virtuous”. Even today this misinterpretation survives, as the following remarks from H.A. Korff, Geist der Goethezeit, II, 298 t. show: “there is no doubting, then, that a man acts morally only when he suppresses his inclinations from a sense of duty. About this Schiller and Kant…agree completely...” O. Walzel expresses much the same view in his introduction to Schiller’s Philosophische Schriften (Säkular-Ausgabe) XI, xl: “Kant’s categorical imperative demands of men that they should let each of their actions be preceded by a struggle in which the law of duty prevails over sensuous inclinations”.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Religion within the Bounds of Reason Alone, pp. 29/30.

    Google Scholar 

  35. Ibid., p. 36.

    Google Scholar 

  36. Ibid., p. 22.

    Google Scholar 

  37. Ibid., p. 32.

    Google Scholar 

  38. First published in Neue Thalia (1793). References are to Schillers Philosophische Schriften und Gedichte, ed. Eugen Kühnemann, 3rd edition (Leipzig, 1922), pp. 95–157.

    Google Scholar 

  39. Ibid., p. 131.

    Google Scholar 

  40. Ibid., pp. 130/1.

    Google Scholar 

  41. Ibid., p. 128.

    Google Scholar 

  42. Ibid., pp. 128/9.

    Google Scholar 

  43. Ibid., p. 132.

    Google Scholar 

  44. Ibid., p. 129. The expression “the conformity of a will to duty” is not here in keeping with Kant’s usage. “Conformity to duty” is Kant’s German expression for mere “legality”, that is, for the outward accordance of an action with duty, and Schiller (as the context shows) obviously means “morality”, that is, conduct “from a sense of duty”.

    Google Scholar 

  45. Ibid., p. 129.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Ibid., p. 130.

    Google Scholar 

  47. Ibid., pp. 129/30.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Ibid., p. 133.

    Google Scholar 

  49. Ibid., p. 134.

    Google Scholar 

  50. Ibid., p. 136.

    Google Scholar 

  51. Ibid., pp. 139/40.

    Google Scholar 

  52. Ibid., p. 141.

    Google Scholar 

  53. Ibid., p. 149.

    Google Scholar 

  54. Ibid., p. 133.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Ibid., p. 148.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Cf. the end of § 3 above.

    Google Scholar 

  57. Kant’s rigorism, as we have said, consists in the view that there is no intermediate between good and evil, and that inclination is therefore an evil incentive, and must be resisted, even when it would actuate us jointly with respect for the law. Schiller objects to this, it is true. But Schiller did not want to prove merely that the concurrence of inclination and duty as motives was not evil, or that there was an intermediate between good and evil. Schiller believed, and he was concerned to show, that the concurrence of inclination as an incentive with the incentive of duty could be morally good; and this does not at all make him a “latitudinarian” such as Kant contrasts with the “rigorist” (Religion, p. 22). Schiller has therefore every right to hope that he has not become a latitudinarian by representing the claims of sensibility (On Grace and Dignity, p. 129). But, because Kant opened his answer to Schiller with the catch-phrase “rigorist manner of decision-making”, his ethics has since been spoken of generally as a rigorism not in the sense in which he defined the term, but in the light of his disagreement with Schiller, that is, as a rejection of the idea that inclination can have a moral function.

    Google Scholar 

  58. On Grace and Dignity, pp. 130/1.

    Google Scholar 

  59. Ibid., p. 130.

    Google Scholar 

  60. Critique of Pure Reason, B 838 t.; cf. Groundwork, p. 438 b.

    Google Scholar 

  61. Groundwork, p. 401 n.

    Google Scholar 

  62. The Metaphysics of Morals, p. 380 m.

    Google Scholar 

  63. Ibid., pp. 401–403 and 448 ff.; cf. Critique of Practical Reason, p. 83.

    Google Scholar 

  64. Vorländer, Kant, Schiller, Goethe, 2nd impression p. 103.

    Google Scholar 

  65. Cf. § 1 above.

    Google Scholar 

  66. H. Cysarz’s judgement of what has been written about Schiller’s relation as a “theoretician” to Kant is therefore not unfair: “The very greatest part of what has been printed on this question is utterly worthless”. Schiller, p. 44.

    Google Scholar 

  67. Cf. O.F. Bollnow’s essay “Was heißt einen Schriftsteller besser verstehen, als er sich selbst verstanden hat?” Deutsche Vierteljahresschrift für Literaturwissenschaft und Geistesgeschichte (1940), pp. 117 ff. Reprinted in Bollnow, Das Verstehen (Mainz, 1949).

    Google Scholar 

  68. Critique of Judgement, § 59.

    Google Scholar 

  69. On Grace and Dignity, p. 130.

    Google Scholar 

  70. Bruno Bauch notices (Vorländer and Kühnemann do not) that Schiller contradicts himself by making this demand. Cf. Bauch, “Schiller und die Idee der Freiheit”, Kantstudien X (1905), pp. 356 and 360. However he touches on this point only very briefly, and rejects Schiller’s demand out of hand as inconsistent with Kantian principles. Bauch praises Schiller then only for urging us “to esteem all of a man”, which demand compensated Kant’s having paid too little attention to the “extra-moral sphere” (Ibid., p. 363).

    Google Scholar 

  71. Die Religion innerhalb der Grenzen der reinen Vernunft, ed. Vorländer, p. LXIV; cf. Lose Blätter aus Kants Nachlaß.

    Google Scholar 

  72. Cf. especially at p. 107 b. in On Grace and Dignity: “The domain of the mind extends (sc. in man) as far as nature is alive (sc. in him)... Not only the tools of the will, but tools that the will has no power to command directly, are influenced at least indirectly by it. The mind governs them not only intentionally, when it acts, but also unintentionally, when it feels”.

    Google Scholar 

  73. Ibid., p. 133.

    Google Scholar 

  74. Schillers philosophische Schriften und Gedichte, p. 50.

    Google Scholar 

  75. H.A. Korff’s account in Geist der Goethezeit (Leipzig, 1927–29) II, 298 is fairly ac- curate on this point, though he does use the terms “morality” and “moral” without resolving their ambiguity entirely.

    Google Scholar 

  76. Friedrich Schiller, On the Aesthetic Education of Man - in a Series of Letters, ed. and trans. Elizabeth M. Wilkinson and L.A. Willoughby (Oxford, 1967), p. 215.

    Google Scholar 

  77. Ibid., p. 217.

    Google Scholar 

  78. Ibid., p. 219.

    Google Scholar 

  79. Ibid., p. 187.

    Google Scholar 

  80. I thank Prof. Dr. Herbert Cysarz for calling my attention to the letter. Vorländer, as I later discovered, also quotes from it in Kant, Schiller, Goethe, p. 42.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1983 Martinus Nijhoff Publishers, The Hague

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Reiner, H. (1983). Kant’s System of Ethics in its Relation to Schiller’s Ethical Views. In: Duty and Inclination The Fundamentals of Morality Discussed and Redefined with Special Regard to Kant and Schiller. Phaenomenologica, vol 93. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-6830-1_1

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-6830-1_1

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-009-6832-5

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-009-6830-1

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics