Advertisement

Substance and Kind: Reflections on the New Theory of Reference

  • Steven E. Boër
Part of the Synthese Library book series (SYLI, volume 178)

Abstract

The traditional doctrine of intension and extension, enshrined in nearly every elementary logic text (under the heading “Definitions”), is a litany of comfortable words. The extension of a (singular or general) term is, we are told, the class of things “it applies to”, and its intension is that associated feature of the term in virtue of which it so applies—roughly, an assemblage of non-question-begging necessary conditions which are jointly sufficient for the term’s application. For most purposes, it is said, talk about the “meaning” of a term may be construed as talk about its intension: in particular, “knowing the meaning of a term” may be construed as knowledge of its intension, i.e., having a “mental representation” of the necessary-and-sufficient condition for its application. This beguilingly simple picture has undergone much technical refinement in the hands of logicians, whose formal implementations have contributed to its long and unbroken reign among semantic theorists.

Keywords

Natural Kind Theoretical Term Conclude That Mass Noun Natural Kind Term 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. Boër, S.: forthcoming, ‘Names and Attitudes’, in M. Salmon (ed.),The Philosophy of Logical Mechanism, D. Reidel, Dordrecht, Holland.Google Scholar
  2. Browning, D.: 1978, ‘Believing in Natural Kinds’,The South-western Journal of Philosophy 9, 135–148.Google Scholar
  3. Carlson, G.: 1977,Reference to Kinds in English, University of Massachusetts Doctoral Dissertation, reproduced by Indiana University Linguistics Club.Google Scholar
  4. Cocchiarella, N.: 1976, ‘On the Logic of Natural Kinds’,Philosophy of Science 43, 202–222.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Cook, M.: 1980, ‘If “Cat” is a Rigid Designator, What Does it Designate?’,Philosophical Studies 37, 61–64.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Dampier, W.: 1929, AHistory of Science. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.Google Scholar
  7. Donellan, K.: 1973, ‘Substances as Individuals’,Journal of Philosophy 70, 711–712.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. Dupre, J.: 1980, ‘Natural Kinds and Biological Taxa’,The Philosophical Review 90, 66–90.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Enc, B.: 1976, ‘Reference of Theoretical Terms’,NOUS 10, 261–282.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Evans, G.: 1973, G.: 1973, ‘The Causal Theory of Names’, in Schwartz [ 1977 ].Google Scholar
  11. Fine, A. : 1975, ‘How to Compare Theories: Reference and Change’,NOUS 9, 17–32.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Goldman, A.: 1979, ‘Reference and Linguistic Authority,’The Southern Journal of Philosophy 17, 305–321.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Goosens, W.: 1977, W.: 1977, ‘Underlying Trait Terms’, in Schwartz [ 1977 ].Google Scholar
  14. Hollinger, R. : 1974, ‘Natural Kinds, Family Resemblances, and Conceptual Change’,The Personalist 55, 323–333.Google Scholar
  15. Kornblith, H.: 1980, ‘Referring to Artifacts’,The Philosophical Review 89, 109–114.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Kripke, S.: 1972, ‘Naming and Necessity’, in D. Davidson and G. Harman (eds.)Semantics of Natural Language. D. Reidel, Dordrecht, Holland.Google Scholar
  17. Kripke, S.: 1977, ‘Speaker’s Reference and Semantic Reference’,Midwest Studies in Philosophy 2, 255–276.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Kripke, S.: 1979, ‘A Puzzle About Belief’, in A. Margalit (ed.)Meaning and Use. D. Reidel, Dordrecht, Holland.Google Scholar
  19. Linsky, B.: 1977, ‘Putnam on the Meaning of Natural Kind Terms’,Canadian Journal of Philosophy 7, 819–828.Google Scholar
  20. Mackie, J.: 1974, ‘Locke’s Anticipation of Kripke’,Analysis 34, 177–180.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. McGinn, C.: 1975, ‘A Note on the Essence of Natural Kinds’,Analysis 35, 177–183.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. McGinn, C.: 1976, ‘On the Necessity of Origin’,Journal of Philosophy 73, 127–135.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. McKay, T. and C. Stern: 1979, ‘Natural Kind Terms and Standards of Membership’,Linguistics and Philosophy 3, 27–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Mellor, D.: 1977, ‘Natural Kinds’, BritishJournal for the Philosophy of Science 28, 299–312.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Moravcsik, J.: 1981, ‘How Do Words Get Their Meanings?’,Journal of Philosophy 78, 5–24.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Pratt, V.: 1972, ‘Biological Classification’,British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 23, 305–327.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  27. Putnam, H.: 1962, ‘The Analytic and the Synthetic’, in H. Feigl and G. Maxwell (eds.)Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 3, University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis (reprinted as chapter 2 of Putnam [1975d]).Google Scholar
  28. Putnam, H.: 1970a, ‘On Properties’, in N. Rescher et al. (eds.)Essays in Honor of Carl G. Hempel. D. Reidel, Dordrecht, Holland (reprinted as chapter 19 of Putnam [1975c]).Google Scholar
  29. Putnam, H.: 1970b, ‘Is Semantics Possible?’, in H. Kiefer and M. Munitz (eds.) Language. Belief. and Metaphysics. State University of New York Press (reprinted as chapter 8 of Putnam [1975d]).Google Scholar
  30. Putnam, H.: 1973: ‘Explanation and Reference’, in G. Pearce and P. Maynard (eds.),Conceptual Change. D. Reidel, Dordrecht, Holland (reprinted as chapter 11 of Putnam [1975d]).Google Scholar
  31. Putnam, H.: 1975a, ‘The Meaning of “Meaning”’, in K. Gunderson (ed.)Language. Mind and Knowledge. University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis (reprinted as chapter 12 of Putnam [1975d]).Google Scholar
  32. Putnam, H.: 1975b, ‘Language and Reality’, in Putnam [I975d], chapter 13.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Putnam, H.: 1975c,Mathematics, Matter, and Method: Philosophical Papers. vol. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.Google Scholar
  34. Putnam, H.: 1975d,Mind, Language and Reality: Philosophical Papers. vol. 2, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  35. Putnam, H.: 1978,Meaning and the Moral Sciences. Routledge and Kegan Paul, Boston.Google Scholar
  36. Salmon, N.: 1979, ‘How Not to Derive Essentialism from the Theory of Reference’,Journal of Philosophy 76, 703–725.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Schwartz, S. (ed.): 1977,Naming, Necessity and Natural Kinds. Cornell University Press, Ithaca, N.Y.Google Scholar
  38. Schwartz, S.: 1978, ‘Putnam on Artifacts’,Philosophical Review 87, 566–574.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Schwartz, S.: 1979, ‘Natural Kind Terms’,Cognition 7, 301–315.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Schwartz, S.: 1980a, ‘Natural Kinds and Nominal Kinds’,Mind 89, 182–195.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  41. Schwartz, S.: 1980b, ‘Formal Semantics and Natural Kind Terms’,Philosophical Studies 38, 189–198.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Teller, P.: 1977, ‘Indicative Introduction’,Philosophical Studies 31, 173–195.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  43. Ware, R.: 1978, ‘The Division of Linguistic Labor and Speaker Competence’,Philosophical Studies 34, 37–61.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  44. Wiggins, D.: 1980,Sameness and Substance. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.Google Scholar
  45. Zemach, E.: 1976, ‘Putnam’s Theory on the Reference of Substance Terms’,Journal of Philosophy 73, 116–127.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© D. Reidel Publishing Company 1985

Authors and Affiliations

  • Steven E. Boër

There are no affiliations available

Personalised recommendations