Skip to main content
  • 83 Accesses

Abstract

There are many theoretical ghosts haunting supposedly factual research programs. One of these specters, positivism, was allegedly put to rest some twenty years ago by Hanson, Kuhn, Polanyi, Toulmin, and others.1 It has reappeared recently, in the work of some social scientists, engineers, and lawmakers who do technology assessments, environmental-impact analyses, and studies of science policy. The positivistic doctrine which some of these scholars promote is that technology assessments (TA’s), environmental-impact analyses (EIA’s), and other science-related studies ought to be wholly neutral and objective descriptions of the facts, and ought not to include any normative, evaluative, or theoretical components. As such, this position really comes down to two theses: (1) that wholly neutral and objective technology assessments and environmental-impact analyses are possible, and (2) that they are desirable. This latter thesis is particularly disturbing, since it amounts to proscribing the role of the normative scholar in TA and EIA and to condemning the attempts of applied philosophers to come to grips with some of the issues of ethics and scientific methodology which are at the heart of policy questions.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. See Norwood Russell Hanson, Patterns of Discovery, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1958

    Google Scholar 

  2. Thomas S. Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 1962, 1979

    Google Scholar 

  3. Michael Polanyi, Personal Knowledge, Harper and Row, New York, 1958, 1964

    Google Scholar 

  4. and Stephen Toulmin, Foresight and Understanding, Harper and Row, New York, 1961.

    Google Scholar 

  5. According to N. Abbagnano, ‘Positivism’, in The Encyclopedia of Philosophy (ed. by Paul Edwards), Macmillan, New York, 1967, vol. 6, p. 414, “the characteristic theses of positivism are that science is the only valid knowledge and facts the only possible objects of knowledge; that philosophy does not possess a method different from science.... Positivism, consequently... opposes any... procedure of investigation that is not reducible to scientific method”. As Laudan points out, because they have disallowed talk about developments in “metaphysics, logic [and] ethics… ‘positivist’ [sociologists,] philosophers and historians of science who see the progress of science entirely in empirical terms have completely missed the huge significance of these developments for science as well as for philosophy”. (Progress and Its Problems: Toward a Theory of Scientific Growth, University of California Press, Berkeley, 1977, pp. 61–62.)

    Google Scholar 

  6. Quoted by C. V. Kidd, ‘Technology Assessment in the Executive Office of the President’, in Technology Assessment: Understanding the Social Consequences of Technological Applications (ed. by R. G. Kasper), Praeger, New York, 1972, p. 131.

    Google Scholar 

  7. US Congress, Office of Technology Assessment, Annual Report to the Congress for 1976, US Government Printing Office, Washington, D.C., 1976, p. 63; hereafter cited as: AR 76.

    Google Scholar 

  8. US Congress, Office of Technology Assessment, Technology Assessment in Business and Government, US Government Printing Office, Washington, D.C., 1977, p. 9; hereafter cited as TA in BG.

    Google Scholar 

  9. L. H. Mayo, ‘The Management of Technology Assessment’, in Kasper, op. cit., p. 107, and R. A. Carpenter, ‘Technology Assessment and the Congress’, in Kasper, op. cit., p. 40.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Dorothy Nelkin, ‘Wisdom, Expertise, and the Application of Ethics’, Science, Technology, and Human Values 6 (34), (Spring (1981), 16–17; hereafter cited as: Nelkin, Ethics. Inasmuch as Nelkin condemns philosophical discussion of the “rights and wrongs” of science policy, she disallows talk about the ethics of science policy. Hence her disallowing this talk about ethics is tantamount to subscribing to a positivistic model of the role of philosophy and of studies about science and technology.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Carpenter, op. cit., p. 42.

    Google Scholar 

  12. M. D. Reagan, Science and the Federal Patron, Oxford University Press, New York, 1969, p. 9.

    Google Scholar 

  13. See Helen Longino, ‘Beyond “Bad Science”: Skeptical Reflections on the Value-Freedom of Scientific Inquiry’, unpublished essay, March 1982, done with the assistance of National Science Foundation Grant OSS 8018095. Hereafter cited as: Longino, Science.

    Google Scholar 

  14. See Longino, Science, esp. pp. 2–3.

    Google Scholar 

  15. For discussion of these three examples from the history of science, see Harold I. Brown, Perception, Theory and Commitment, University of Chicago Press, Chicago,1977, pp. 97–100, 147, and

    Google Scholar 

  16. K. S. Shrader-Frechette, ‘Recent Changes in the Concept of Matter: How Does “Elementary Particle” Mean?’, in Philosophy of Science Association 1980, vol. 1 (ed. by P. D. Asquith and R. N. Giere), Philosophy of Science Association, East Lansing, 1980, pp. 302 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Longino, Science, pp. 6–9.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Longino, Science, pp. 10–12.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Longino, Science, pp. 16–19.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Longino, Science, p. 25.

    Google Scholar 

  21. W. K. Foell, ‘Assessment of Energy/Environment Systems’, in Environmental Assessment of Socioeconomic Systems (ed. by D. F. Burkhardt and W. H. Ittelson), Plenum, New York, 1978, p. 196

    Google Scholar 

  22. US Congress, Technology Assessment Activities in the Industrial, Academic, and Governmental Communities, Hearings Before the Technology Assessment Board of the Office of Technology Assessment, 94th Congress, Second Session, June 8–10 and 14, 1976, US Government Printing Office, Washington, D.C., 1976, pp. 66, 200, 220; hereafter cited as: TA in IAG.

    Google Scholar 

  23. See A. B. Lovins, ‘Cost-Risk-Benefit Assessments in Energy Policy’, George Washington Law Review 5 (45), (August 1977), 940.

    Google Scholar 

  24. See M. C. Tool, The Discretionary Economy: A Normative Theory of Political Economy, Goodyear, Santa Monica, Ca, 1979, p. 279.

    Google Scholar 

  25. See R. M. Hare, ‘Contrasting Methods of Environmental Planning’, in Ethics and the Problems of the 21st Century (ed. by K. E. Goodpaster and K. M. Sayre), University of Notre Dame Press, Notre Dame, In., 1979, p. 65.

    Google Scholar 

  26. See Tool, op. cit., p. 280.

    Google Scholar 

  27. For statements of the OTA’s belief, see US Congress, Office of Technology Assessment, Annual Report to the Congress for 1976, US Government Printing Office, Washington, D.C., 1976, p. 4

    Google Scholar 

  28. and US Congress, Office of Technology Assessment, Annual Report to the Congress for 1978, US Government Printing Office, Washington, D.C., 1978, p. 7;hereafter cited as: AR76 and AR78, respectively.

    Google Scholar 

  29. A. L. Macfie, ‘Welfare in Economic Theory’, The Philosophical Quarterly 3 (10), (January 1953), 59, makes this same point.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  30. H. P. Green, ‘The Adversary Process in Technology Assessment’, in Kasper, op. cit., pp. 51, 52, 55, 60, 61; hereafter cited as: Green, Adversary; and H. Fox, Chair, Technology Assessment: State of the Field, Second Report of the Technology Assessment Panel of the Engineers Joint Council, Engineers Joint Council, New York, 1976, pp. 3–5

    Google Scholar 

  31. and S. G. Burns, ‘Congress and the Office of Technology Assessment’, George Washington Law Review 5 (45), (August 1977), 1146.

    Google Scholar 

  32. A. D. Biderman, ‘Social Indicators and Goals’, in Social Indicators (ed. by R. A. Bauer), MIT Press, Cambridge Ma., 1966, p. 101.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Sergio Koreisha and Robert Stobaugh, ‘Appendix: Limits to Models’, in Energy Future: Report of the Energy Project at the Harvard Business School (ed. by Robert Stobaugh and Daniel Yergin), Random House, New York, 1979, pp. 237–240.

    Google Scholar 

  34. Mr. Selwyn Enzer, speaking before the committee, as quoted in Congress, OTA, TA in IAG, p. 225, makes this same point.

    Google Scholar 

  35. The OTA itself admits this. See Congress, OTA, TA in BG, p. 13; Congress, OTA, AR76, pp. 63, 66.

    Google Scholar 

  36. For discussion of this topic, see K. S. Shrader-Frechette, ‘Technology Assessment as Applied Philosophy of Science’, Science, Technology, and Human Values 6 (33), (Fall 1980), 33–50; hereafter cited as: Technology Assessment.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  37. H. Green, ‘Cost-Risk-Benefit Assessment and the Law: Introduction and Perspective’, George Washington Law Review 5 (45), (August, 1977), 908

    Google Scholar 

  38. hereafter cited as: Cost. See also T. Means, ‘The Concorde Calculus’, George Washington Law Review 5 (45), (August 1977), 1037.

    Google Scholar 

  39. See Lovins, op. cit., pp. 913–937; W. D. Rowe, An Anatomy of Risk, John Wiley, New York, 1977, pp. 145–147, 225, 243

    Google Scholar 

  40. and A. L. Porter, F. A. Rossini, S. R. Carpenter, and A. T. Roper, A Guidebook for Technology Assessment and Impact Assessment, North Holland, New York, 1980, pp. 266–267, all of whom discuss these points.

    Google Scholar 

  41. For an example of someone who holds this position, see C. Starr, Current Issues in Energy, Pergamon, New York, 1979, p. 10; hereafter cited as: CIE.

    Google Scholar 

  42. D. J. Epp, et al., Identification and Specification of Inputs for Benefit-Cost Modeling of Pesticide Use, EPA-600/5–77–012, US Environmental Protection Agency, Washington, D.C., 1977, p. 26, makes a similar point.

    Google Scholar 

  43. A. V. Kneese, S. Ben-David, and W. D. Schulze, ‘The Ethical Foundations of Benefit-Cost Analysis Techniques’, in Energy and the Future (ed. by D. MacLean and P. G. Brown), Rowman and Littlefield, Totowa, N.J., 1982, pp. 59–73.

    Google Scholar 

  44. K. Shrader-Frechette, ‘Economic Analyses of Energy Options: A Critical Assessment of Some Recent Studies’, in Energy and Ecological Modelling (ed. by W. Mitsch, W. Bosserman, and J. Klopatek), Elsevier, New York, 1981, pp. 773–778.

    Google Scholar 

  45. D. Okrent, ‘A General Evaluation Approach to Risk-Benefit...’, UCLA-ENG-7777, UCLA School of Eng., Los Angeles, 1977, pp. 1–9.

    Google Scholar 

  46. Rowe, op. cit., p. 3, and W. Häfele, ‘Benefit-Risk Tradeoffs in Nuclear Power Generation’, in Energy and the Environment: A Risk-Benefit Approach (ed. by H. Ashley, R. Rudman, and C. Whipple), Pergamon, New York, 1976, p. 181.

    Google Scholar 

  47. US Nuclear Regulatory Commission, Reactor Safety Study: An Assessment of Accident Risks in US Commercial Nuclear Power Plants (WASH-1400), US Government Printing Office, Washington, D.C., 1975, Appendix XI, p.2–2; hereafter cited as: WASH-1400.

    Google Scholar 

  48. See, for example, C. Starr, ‘Benefit-Cost Studies in Sociotechnical Systems’, in Perspectives on Benefit-Risk Decision Making (ed. by the Committee on Public Engineering Policy), National Academy of Engineering, Washington, D.C., 1972, pp. 26–27.

    Google Scholar 

  49. See, for example, B. Fischhoff, P. Slovic, S. Lichtenstein, S. Read, and B. Combs, ‘How Safe is Safe Enough?’, Policy Sciences 9 (2), (1978), 150

    Article  Google Scholar 

  50. and P. Slovic, B. Fischhoff, and S. Lichtenstein, ‘Facts and Fears: Understanding Perceived Risk’, in Societal Risk Assessment (ed. by R. Schwing and W. Albers), Plenum, New York, 1980, pp. 190–192.

    Google Scholar 

  51. See K. Boulding, Economics as a Science, McGraw-Hill, New York, 1970

    Google Scholar 

  52. and E. J. Mishan, ‘Whatever Happened to Progress?’ Journal of Economic Issues 2 (12), (1978), 405–425.

    Google Scholar 

  53. See also K. Shrader-Frechette, Environmental Ethics, Boxwood, Pacific Grove, 1981, pp. 135–36, 212–216.

    Google Scholar 

  54. A. D. Biderman, ‘Anticipatory Studies and Stand-by Research Capabilities’, in Bauer, op. cit., pp. 272, makes these same points.

    Google Scholar 

  55. Biderman, op. cit., pp. 273–274.

    Google Scholar 

  56. Biderman, ‘Social Indicators and Goals’, in Bauer, op. cit., p. 97, makes the same point, as does Oskar Morgenstern, On the Accuracy of Economic Observations, Princeton University Press, Princeton, 1963, pp. 26, 35–37, 62, 194–107.

    Google Scholar 

  57. E. Lawless, Technology and Social Shock, Rutgers University Press, New Brunswick, N.J., 1977, pp. 497–498.

    Google Scholar 

  58. Epp et al., pp. 111, 73–78.

    Google Scholar 

  59. One problem with most assessments of carcinogens, for example, is that a test result of 0 tumors in 100 animals is statistically consistent with a true risk of 4.5% when an assurance level of 99% is employed. (See Epp et al., p. 55.) Another area in which similar statistical problems and difficulties with extrapolation occur is radiation hazards. Dose-response coefficients are determined by making a theoretical assumption (generally, that dose-response is linear) about the validity of extrapolating on the basis of high doses (See US Atomic Energy Commission, Comparative Risk-Cost-Benefit Study of Alternative Sources of Electrical Energy, WASH-1224, US Government Printing Office, Washington, D.C., 1974, pp. 4–13, to 4–15.

    Google Scholar 

  60. See. S. G. Hadden, ‘DES and the Assignment of Risk’, in Controversy: Politics of Technical Decisions (ed. by D. Nelkin), Sage, Beverly Hills, pp. 118–119.

    Google Scholar 

  61. This point is documented by S. Hadden, op. cit., pp. 122–123.

    Google Scholar 

  62. US Environmental Protection Agency, Proceedings of a Public Forum on Environmental Protection Criteria for Radioactive Waste, ORP/CSD-78–2, US EPA, Washington, D.C., 1978, p. 121, letter from Dr. Thomas Mancuso. See also pp. 122–123, and I. Bross, Director of Biostatistics at Roswell Park Memorial Institute, in Committee on Commerce, Science, and Transportation, Radiation Health and Safety, US Senate, 95th Congress, First Session, No. 9549, US Government Printing Office, Washington, D.C., 1977, pp. 176–177. For information on US radiation standards, see

    Google Scholar 

  63. K. S. Shrader-Frechette, Nuclear Power and Public Policy, Reidel, Boston, 1983, Chapter 2.

    Google Scholar 

  64. G. J. Lieberman, ‘Fault-Tree Analysis as an Example of Risk Methodology’, in Ashley, et al., op. cit., pp. 247–276, also discusses this point.

    Google Scholar 

  65. R. Zeckhauser, ‘Procedures for Valuing Lives’, Public Policy 4 (23), (Fall 1975), 444.

    Google Scholar 

  66. Burns, op. cit., p. 1150.

    Google Scholar 

  67. Dr. Don E. Kash, Director of the Science and Public Policy Program, University of Oklahoma, in Congress, OTA, TA in IAG.

    Google Scholar 

  68. See note 5. H. Skolimowski, ‘Technology Assessment as a Critique of Civilization’, in PSA 1974 (ed. by R. S. Cohen, et al.), D. Reidel, Boston, 1976, p. 461, points to a similar condemnation of applied ethics and normative policy analysis. He cites an article by Genevieve J. Knezo, ‘Technology Assessment: A Bibliographic Review’, which was published in the first issue of the periodical, Technology Assessment. He says that Knezo condemns all normative literature as “emotional, neoluddite, and polemic” in nature, and “designed to arouse and mold mass public opinion”. At the same time, says Skolimowski, Knezo praises all allegedly “neutral” work, and says it “usefully serves inform the public, through a responsible press, of the pros and cons of a public issue of national importance”.

    Google Scholar 

  69. See Nelkin, Ethics, pp. 16–17, for an example of someone who holds this position. See note 51.

    Google Scholar 

  70. For two quite diverse views of future energy consumption, see Ford Foundation, Final Report, Energy Policy Project, A Time to Choose, Ballinger, Cambridge, Massachusetts, 1974, and W. G. Dupree and J. S. Corsentino, United States Energy through the Year 2000 (revised), US Department of the Interior, Bureau of Mines, Washington, D.C., 1975.

    Google Scholar 

  71. See Dupree and Corsentino, op. cit.

    Google Scholar 

  72. See note 45. See also Skolimowski, op. cit., p. 461.

    Google Scholar 

  73. C. H. Weiss and M. J. Bucuvalas, Social Science Research and Decision Making, Columbia University Press, New York, 1980, p. 26, makes this same point.

    Google Scholar 

  74. For another discussion of this same point, see E. S. Quade, Analysis for Public Decisions, American Elsevier, New York, 1975, pp. 269 ff.

    Google Scholar 

  75. This same point is also made by C. E. Lindblom and D. K. Cohen, Usable Knowledge: Social Science and Social Problem Solving, Yale University Press, New Haven, 1979, p. 64.

    Google Scholar 

  76. See notes 5 and 51.

    Google Scholar 

  77. See, for example, Shrader-Frechette, Technology Assessment, pp. 35–38.

    Google Scholar 

  78. Nelkin, Ethics, p. 17, argues that scholars ought to engage in nonevaluative description. See also Knezo (note 51).

    Google Scholar 

  79. See R. M. Hare, ‘Contrasting Methods of Environmental Planning’, in Goodpaster and Sayre, op. cit., p. 76, who outlines this rationale of positivists.

    Google Scholar 

  80. See John Caiazzo, ‘Analyzing the Social “Scientist”’, The Intercollegiate Review 2 (16), (Spring/Summer 1981), 96.

    Google Scholar 

  81. Nelkin, Ethics, p. 17.

    Google Scholar 

  82. Ruth Benedict, cited in Caiazzo, op. cit., p. 96.

    Google Scholar 

  83. For an account of this episode, see Albert Einstein, Ideas and Opinions (trans, by S. Bergmann), Crown, New York, 1954, pp. 205–210

    Google Scholar 

  84. Albert Einstein, The World As I See It (trans, by A. Harris), Philosophical Library, New York, 1949, pp. 81–89

    Google Scholar 

  85. and Philipp Frank, Einstein: His Life and Times (trans, by G. Rosen), Alfred A. Knopf, New York, 1947, pp. 234–235.

    Google Scholar 

  86. Notebooks (trans, by J. O’Brien), Knopf, New York, 1965, p. 146.

    Google Scholar 

  87. Quoted by J. Primack and F. von Hippel, Advice and Dissent: Scientists in the Political Arena, Basic, New York, 1974.

    Google Scholar 

  88. See, for example, W. D. Ross, The Right and the Good, Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1930, Chapter 2.

    Google Scholar 

  89. Congress, OTA, TA in IAG, pp. 233–234.

    Google Scholar 

  90. D. Dickson, The Politics of Alternative Technology, Universe Books, New York, 1975, p. 189, makes a similar point: “the stress placed on the cultural importance of abstract science legitimates the ideology of scientism, yet disguises not only the exploitative way in which science is put to practical use through technology, but also the very fact that the existence of contemporary science — in terms of support for R and D — results directly from this practical use. A further aspect of scientism is that it promotes a passive acceptance of an existing state of affairs.… It dismisses as irrational or unscientific any attempts to challenge our contemporary situation in terms of the class interests which it maintains”. See also pp. 186–195.

    Google Scholar 

  91. Nelkin, Ethics, pp. 16–17.

    Google Scholar 

  92. W. Häfele, ‘Energy’, in Science, Technology, and the Human Prospect (ed. by C. Starr and P. Ritterbush), Pergamon, New York, 1979, p. 139.

    Google Scholar 

  93. For arguments to this effect, see K. Shrader-Frechette, ‘Economics, Risk-Cost-Benefit Analysis, and the Linearity Assumption’, in PSA 1982, Volume 1 (ed. by P. D. Asquith and T. Nickles), Edwards, Ann Arbor, Michigan, pp. 219–220; hereafter cited as: Economics.

    Google Scholar 

  94. For arguments to support this claim, see K. Shrader-Frechette, Economics, pp. 219–223.

    Google Scholar 

  95. R. Kasper, ‘Perceptions of Risk and their Effects on Decision Making’, in Societal Risk Assessment (ed. by R. Schwing and W. Albers), Plenum, New York, 1980, p. 77, makes the same point.

    Google Scholar 

  96. H. Green, Cost, p. 901, makes this same point.

    Google Scholar 

  97. M. Lutz and K. Lux, The Challenge of Humanistic Economics, Benjamin/Cummings, London, 1979, p. 3, makes the same point.

    Google Scholar 

  98. L. Winner, Autonomous Technology, The MIT Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, 1977, pp. 10–11.

    Google Scholar 

  99. Cited by Tool, op. cit., p. xvi.

    Google Scholar 

  100. R. Andrews, ‘Substantive Guidelines for Environmental Impact Assessments’, in Environmental Impact Analysis (ed. by R. Jain and B. Hutchings), University of Illinois Press, Urbana, 1978, p. 40, substantiates this point, as does B. Gross, ‘The State of the Nation: Social Systems Accounting’, in Bauer, op. cit., p. 165.

    Google Scholar 

  101. Gross, op. cit., pp. 268–271.

    Google Scholar 

  102. Gross, op. cit., pp. 266, also holds this position.

    Google Scholar 

  103. Lovins, op. cit., pp. 941—942; Green, Cost, p. 910, and Green, Adversary. See also S. Enzer, Associate Director, Center for Futures Research, Graduate School of Business, University of Southern California, op. cit., p. 235 (note 17);Biderman, op. cit., p. 134; Congress, OTA, TA in IAG, p. 198, statement by D. Kash, Director of the Science and Public Policy Program, University of Oklahoma; and A. Kantrowitz, ‘Democracy and Technology’, in Starr and Ritterbush, op. cit., pp. 199–211.

    Google Scholar 

  104. M. Bauser, ‘The Atomic Energy Commission’s ECCS Rule-Making’, Atomic Energy Law Review 1 (16), (Spring 1974), 74, for example, says that the “adversary system of trial… is not compatible with an objective presentation and scholarly, detached evaluation of technical information”.

    Google Scholar 

  105. H. Green, Adversary, p. 58, defends this point.

    Google Scholar 

  106. Green, Adversary, pp. 58–59, makes many of these same points.

    Google Scholar 

  107. A similar point is made by R. Cohen, ‘Ethics and Science’, in For Dirk Struik, Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, XV (ed. by R. Cohen, J. J. Stachel, and M. W. Wartofsky), D. Reidel, Boston, 1974, p. 310. See also Hare, op. cit., p. 65, and Sko-limowski, op. cit., p. 459, as well as Porter et al, op. cit., p. 255; Lovins, op. cit., p. 936

    Google Scholar 

  108. and J. R. Ravetz, Scientific Knowledge and Its Social Problems, Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1971, pp. 400–401, 431–432.

    Google Scholar 

  109. Nelkin, Ethics, p. 16.

    Google Scholar 

  110. Nelkin, Ethics, p. 16.

    Google Scholar 

  111. Nelkin, Ethics, p. 16.

    Google Scholar 

  112. Robert Stobaugh and Daniel Yergin, ‘The End of Easy Oil’ in Energy Future: Report of the Energy Project at the Harvard Business School (ed. by R. Stobaugh and D. Yergin), Random House, New York, 1979, pp. 4, 6, 11. See also ‘Conclusion: Toward a Balanced Energy Program’ in Stobaugh and Yergin

    Google Scholar 

  113. ibid., p. 227. Also in the same collection, see the essay by M. A. Maidique, ‘Solar America’, p. 211. See also Laudan, op. cit., (Note 1), pp. 59–61.

    Google Scholar 

  114. Nelkin, Ethics, p. 16, ascribes problems to politics rather than to faulty methodology.

    Google Scholar 

  115. G. E. Brown, California, member of the Technology Assessment Board, OTA, in Congress, OTA, TA in IAG, p. 201, has emphasized this point.

    Google Scholar 

  116. Dr. D. Kash, op. cit., p. 202, agrees with this point.

    Google Scholar 

  117. K. E. Boulding, quoted by B. M. Gross, ‘Preface’, in Bauer, op. cit., p. xvii.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1985 D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, Holland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Shrader-Frechette, K.S. (1985). The Retreat from Ethical Analysis. In: Science Policy, Ethics, and Economic Methodology. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-6449-5_3

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-6449-5_3

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-277-1845-7

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-009-6449-5

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics