Advertisement

Confucian Moral Metaphysics and Heidegger’s Fundamental Ontology

  • Wing-Cheuk Chan
Part of the Analecta Husserliana book series (ANHU, volume 17)

Abstract

Confucianism has been the major school of Chinese philosophy. Phenomenology arose in this century and formed a main current in Western philosophy. Thanks to the elaborated reconstruction of traditional Confucianism by Mou Tzung-sana — an important representative of contemporary Confucianism — the moral-metaphysical character of Confucian philosophy was rediscovered. On the other hand, Heidegger’s fundamental ontology has provided us with a radical development of phenomenology.

Keywords

Moral Activity Chinese Philosophy Moral Praxis Confucian Philosophy Fundamental Ontology 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  1. 1.
    Hsin-T’i and Hsing-T’i (in Chinese), 3 vols. (Taipei, 1978); Intellectual Intuition and Chinese Philosophy (in Chinese), (Taipei, 1971); Phenomena and Things- in - themselves (in Chinese) (Taipei, 1975).Google Scholar
  2. 2.
    Being and Time, trans. John Macquirre and Edward Robinson (New York, 1962), p. 34.Google Scholar
  3. 3.
    Sein und Zeit (Tübingen, 1928), p. 147.Google Scholar
  4. 4.
    Ibid., p. 212.Google Scholar
  5. 5.
    The Way back into the Ground of Metaphysics,’ in Existentialism from Dostoevsky to Sartre, ed. and trans. Walter Kaufmann (Ohio, 1956), p. 214.Google Scholar
  6. 6.
    Brief uber den Humanismus,’ in Wegmarken (Frankfurt, 1978), p. 338.Google Scholar
  7. 7.
    Gesamtausgabe, 24:436.Google Scholar
  8. 8.
    Ibid., p. 435.Google Scholar
  9. 9.
    The End of Philosophy, trans. Joan Stambough (New York, 1973), p. xi.Google Scholar
  10. 10.
    Letter to Richardson,’ in Through Phenomenology to Thought, by William Richardson (The Hague, 1963), p. xiii. See also Zur Sache Des Denkens (Tübingen, 1976), p. 30.Google Scholar
  11. 11.
    Gesamtausgabe, 24:436.Google Scholar
  12. 12.
    Zur Sache des Denkens, p. 35.Google Scholar
  13. 13.
    The End of Philosophy, p. xii.Google Scholar
  14. 14.
    Zur Sache des Denkens, p. 36.Google Scholar
  15. 15.
    The End of Philosophy, pp. xi–xii.Google Scholar
  16. 16.
    Die Technik und die Kehre (Pfullingen, 1962), p. 38.Google Scholar
  17. 17.
  18. 18.
    Cf. George Ghanotakis, ‘Heidegger’s Fundamental Phenomenology,’ Man and World 14 (1981): 251–67.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  19. 19.
    Identität und Differenz (Pfullingen, 1957), p. 26.Google Scholar
  20. 20.
    Letter to Richardson,’ p. xxiiGoogle Scholar
  21. 21.
    Introduction to Metaphysics, trans. Ralph Mannheim (New Haven, 1959), p. 196.Google Scholar
  22. 22.
    To be sure, here “ought to be” is essentially an ontological concept, which must be distinguished from H. A. Prichard’s original conception of it in his ‘Does Moral Philosophy Rest on a Mistake?’Google Scholar
  23. 23.
    We adopt the concept of “idealistische Richtungsethik” from Max Müller’s Existenzphilosophie in Geistigen Leben der Gegenwart (Heidelberg, 1964). Furthermore, by “existentiale Seinsethik” we mean a kind of ethics which regards moral praxis as the way of to be or ontological moment of the human being and accordingly as a responce to Being itself.Google Scholar
  24. 24.
    see Michael G. Vater, ‘Heidegger and Schelling: The Finitude of Being,’ Idealistic Studies 5 (1975): 20–58.Google Scholar
  25. 25.
    Gesamtausgabe, 24:180; my italics.Google Scholar
  26. 26.
    The Meanings of Energeia and Entelecheia in Aristotl’s Philosophy’ (in Chinese), Hsüeh-Yüan 1 (l948):17–26.Google Scholar
  27. 27.
    It should be noted that Confucian conception of cosmological creativity is not identical with “Schaffung” (poesis) in the Heideggerian sense. For the latter means nothing but the ontological movement of Being.Google Scholar
  28. 28.
    Kant und die philosophische Hermeneutik,’ Kant-Studien 67 (1976):395.Google Scholar
  29. 29.
    Indeed, Gadamer also writes: “Zwar gait die Kantische Grundlegung der Moralphilo- sophie auf dem Gedanken der Autonomie der parktischen Vernuft und auf dem Kategorischen Imperativ - mit Recht - als eines der grössten Verdienste der Kantischen Philosophie - aber dass diese Grundlegung eine Grundlegung zur ‘Metaphysik’ der Sitten war und eine ‘moralische Metaphysik’wieder in Geltung setze, ktimmerte wening” (ibid.).Google Scholar

Copyright information

© D. Reidel Publishing Company 1984

Authors and Affiliations

  • Wing-Cheuk Chan
    • 1
  1. 1.Tunghai UniversityTaichungTaiwan

Personalised recommendations