Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science ((BSPS,volume 81))

  • 115 Accesses

Abstract

Objective meaning is the relation of a sign to the designated object. Charles Morris used the expression ‘existential meaning,’ but here that expression is unacceptable because of the restricted meaning of the term ‘existential’ in our theory. Semantic philosophers writing in English have used many terms for this dimension of meaning: ‘reference’ (as a translation of Frege’s ‘Bedeutung’), ‘indication’ (Russell), and ‘denotation’ (Mill), to name a few.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 259.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 329.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 329.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Jean Piaget, La repr’sentation du monde chez l’enfant, Presses Universitaires de France; The Child’s Conception of the World, Kegan Paul, 1929.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Hayakawa, Language in Thought and Action, London, 1932, pp. 28–31.

    Google Scholar 

  3. “The man who in the fantastic reality of heaven, where he sought a supernatural being, found only a reflection of himself, will no longer be tempted to find only a semblance of himself, - a non-human being - where he seeks and must seek his genuine reality” (Karl Marx, “Contribution to the Critique of Hegel’s Philosophy of Right: Introduction”, The Marx-Engels Reader, ed. R. C. Tucker, II ed., W. W. Norton, New York, 1978, p. 53.)

    Google Scholar 

  4. “Religion is the general theory of this world, its encyclopedic compendium, its logic in popular form, its spiritual point d’honneur, its enthusiasm, its moral sanction, its solemn complement, its general basis of consolation and justification. It is the fantastic realization of the human being, inasmuch as the human being possesses no true reality. Thus the struggle against religion is an indirect struggle against that world, whose spiritual aroma is religion... Religion is the sigh of an oppressed being, the sentiment of a heartless world, and the soul of soulless conditions. It is the opium of the people” (Ibid., p. 54).

    Google Scholar 

  5. John Wisdom, ‘Logical Constructions,’ Mind, 1931, p. 202.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Gilbert Ryle, ‘Systematically Misleading Expressions,’ Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 1931.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Alfred J. Ayer, ‘Verification and Experience,’ Ibid., 1936–7, also Foundations of Empirical Knowledge, London, 1947, p. 106.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Alfred North Whitehead, Symbolism, Its Meaning and Effect, An Anthology, Northrop and Gross, (eds.), Cambridge, 1953, p. 538.

    Google Scholar 

  9. John Stuart Mill.,A System of Logic, B. I, Ch. II, Section 5, London, 1865, VI ed.

    Google Scholar 

  10. Russell, The Principles of Mathematics, Cambridge, 1903, Section 427.

    Google Scholar 

  11. See Urmson, Philosophical Analysis, Oxford, 1956, pp. 22–3.

    Google Scholar 

  12. Bertrand Russell, ‘On Denoting,’ Mind, 1905.

    Google Scholar 

  13. Gilbert Ryle, ‘The Theory of Meaning,’ British Philosophy in the Mid-Century, London, 1957, pp. 247–8.

    Google Scholar 

  14. Quine, From a Logical Point of View, Cambridge, Mass., 1953.

    Google Scholar 

  15. Ibid., p. 9.

    Google Scholar 

  16. Ibid., p. 130.

    Google Scholar 

  17. Gilbert Ryle, ‘The Theory of Meaning,’ British Philosophy in the Mid-Century, London, 1957, pp. 248–9.

    Google Scholar 

  18. R. W. Ashby, ‘Use and Verification,’ Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society VIII(1956), 140.

    Google Scholar 

  19. Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, Oxford, 1953, Sections 199, 206, 241.

    Google Scholar 

  20. Ibid., Section 81.

    Google Scholar 

  21. Wittgenstein, op. cit., Section 66.

    Google Scholar 

  22. Ibid., Section 97.

    Google Scholar 

  23. Ibid., Section 2.

    Google Scholar 

  24. Russell, An Inquiry into Meaning and Truth, London, 1940, p. 38.

    Google Scholar 

  25. Ibid., p. 79.

    Google Scholar 

  26. It is in this sense that Kant, proceeding upon the conception of mechanical law as the sole form of necessity, considered all the phenomena of life to be unavoidably accidental, asserting that, “nature viewed as a simple mechanism could have developed differently in a thousand ways...” (Kant, Kritik der Urteilskraft, Berlin, 1922, Section 61).

    Google Scholar 

  27. Russell, An Inquiry into Meaning and Truth, New York 1940, p. 25-6.

    Google Scholar 

  28. Tarski, “Der Wahrheitsbegriff in den formalisierten Sprachen,” Studia Philosophica, Vol. 1, 1935, p. 261 – 405.

    Google Scholar 

  29. Bertrand Russell, The Principles of Mathematics, 2nd ed., 1938, p. IX.

    Google Scholar 

  30. “What are invariant relations, what are propositional functions other than possibilities which are capable of being actualized but never require this in order to show their being?” (James Feibleman, A Reply to Bertrand Russell’s Introduction to the Second Edition of ‘The Principles of Mathematics,’ in The Philosophy of Bertrand Russell. The Library of Living Philosophers, Vol. V, Evanston, 1946, p. 161.

    Google Scholar 

  31. Op. cit., p. 159.

    Google Scholar 

  32. Ibid., p. 160.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Russell often asserted that mathematics and philosophy were sciences of a possible world. Wittgenstein made the statement for philosophy as a whole. Our investigation is not directed at phenomena but rather at what might be called the possibilities of phenomena. This means that we think about the type of statements we make about phenomena. (Wittgenstein, Philosophical Investigations, Oxford, 1953, Section 90, p. 42.)

    Google Scholar 

  34. “We can even go so far as to say that in all knowledge that can be expressed in words — with the exception of the words ‘this,’ ‘that,’ and several others whose meaning varies on various occasions – there are no names in the strict sense of the word: what appear as names in fact are descriptions.” (Bertrand Russell, Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy, 2nd ed., London, 1920, ch. XVI, p. 178.)

    Google Scholar 

  35. Op. cit., p. 97.

    Google Scholar 

  36. In the Introduction to Mathematics Russell devotes two chapters to an analysis of the definite article (op. cit., p. 95).

    Google Scholar 

  37. Russell, Introduction to Mathematical Philosophy, p. 173.

    Google Scholar 

  38. Cf. Pap, Elements of Analytical Philosophy, New York, 1949.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1984 D. Reidel Publishing Company

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Marković, M. (1984). Objective Meaning. In: Dialectical Theory of Meaning. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol 81. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-6256-9_9

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-6256-9_9

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-009-6258-3

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-009-6256-9

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics