Skip to main content

Popper on the Difference between the Natural and the Social Sciences

  • Chapter

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science ((BSPS,volume 93))

Abstract

Popper always told us to open a paper with a problem: I have two problems. The first is whether in the years that have elapsed since 1943–1944, when “The Poverty of Historicism” was originally published, there have emerged new arguments to challenge what Popper said about the differences between the natural and the social sciences. To address this problem I have to face a second one: just what, in that work and his other comments on the topic, did Popper consider the main differences between the natural and social sciences to be? Both problems are enmeshed in a sociological problem, that of the strange reception of Popper’s ideas in general,1 and the extraordinary sidestepping of The Poverty of Historicism in particular.

Parts of this essay were read to the Philosophy Department, Claremont Graduate School, Claremont, California, April 22, 1980. I wish to thank my questioners and also Joseph Agassi.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   169.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Notes

  1. Popper’s “Replies to My Critics,” in The Philosophy of Karl Popper, ed. P. A. Schilpp (LaSalle, Ill.: Open Court, 1974), concentrates on the ideational content of the Popper legend. As we shall see, however, the logic of the situation of new ideas has a sociological dimension that can help explain the frustrating misunderstanding and misrepresentation from which Popper has suffered.

    Google Scholar 

  2. Sociological hypothesis: those who deceive themselves into believing they have given up a doctrine will be particularly withering and dismissive of criticism of that doctrine. Compare the reaction of fellow-traveling historicists to Popper with that of fellow-traveling language philosophers to Gellner, not to mention fellow-traveling justificationists to Bartley, fellow-traveling inductivists to Popper again, and so on.

    Google Scholar 

  3. The Poverty of Historicism is, I think, one of my stodgiest pieces of writing. Besides, after I had written the ten sections which form the first chapter, my whole plan broke down.” Popper, “Intellectual Autobiography,” in The Philosophy of Karl Popper, ed. Schilpp, p. 90.

    Google Scholar 

  4. Translated into English and published in late 1959 as The Logic of Scientific Discovery (New York: Basic Books).

    Google Scholar 

  5. In the 1950 “Preface” to the revised edition of The Open Society and Its Enemies, and on p. 91 of the “Autobiography,” Popper writes of the mood of gloom in which that book was written, perhaps fearing the war would be lost by the Allies, a mood that apparently lifted only after his first visit to the United States.

    Google Scholar 

  6. Stalinists use the specious justification of Lenin that you cannot make an omelet without breaking eggs. Breaking human heads and bodies does not yield a pleasant-tasting dish. Alexander Solzhenitsyn’s The Gulag Archipelago (New York: Harper & Row, 1973–1978) systematically shows how in virtually every respect conditions were worse in Lenin’s and Stalin’s Russia than under the czars.

    Google Scholar 

  7. Excellent examples of the latter were given in an article, “Many Benefit as Inflation Goes Higher,” by Martin Baron, Los Angeles Times, March 13, 1980, pp. 1ff.

    Google Scholar 

  8. Thus he is not allied with those who attack the social sciences because of pretentiousness, such as Pitrim Sorokin, C. Wright Mills, A. R. Louch, and Stanislav Andreski. It should be noted that Popper had second thoughts about the Oedipus Effect, as he recalls in the “Autobiography,” pp. 96–97.

    Google Scholar 

  9. See The Poverty of Historicism, secs. 29 and 31, and his “La rationalité et le statut du principe de rationalité,” in Les fondéments philosophiques des systemes economiques, ed. Emil M. Claassen (Paris: Payot, 1967), pp. 142–150.

    Google Scholar 

  10. I have expanded on this in Concepts and Society (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1972), esp. chap. 1.

    Google Scholar 

  11. A bold extension of the method to explain fashion and style is attempted by E. H. Gombrich in “The Logic of Vanity Fair,” in The Philosophy of Karl Popper, ed. Schilpp, pp. 925–957, a paper generously praised by Popper in his “Replies.”

    Google Scholar 

  12. See Alan Musgrave, “Impersonal Knowledge: A Criticism of Subjectivism in Epistemology” (Ph.D. diss., University of London, 1969).

    Google Scholar 

  13. and J. Agassi, Science in Flux (Dordrecht: Reidel 1975), chap. 6.

    Google Scholar 

  14. W. W. Bartley, III, “The Philosophy of Karl Popper: Part I: Biology and Evolutionary Epistemology,” Philosophia 6 (1976): 463–494. [See also his essay in the present volume—Ed.]

    Article  Google Scholar 

  15. It appeared too soon after to be read as a reply to The Poverty of Historicism, and it criticizes Popper on matters (such as social engineering and the unity of method) treated fully only in The Open Society and Its Enemies. Winch’s teacher was Rush Rhees, author of a denunciation of The Open Society and Its Enemies, namely, “Social Engineering,” Mind 56 (1947): 317–331.

    Google Scholar 

  16. The argument is also fully discussed by F. A. Hayek in The Counter-Revolution of Science (Glencoe, Ill.: The Free Press, 1955) (originally in Economica, 1942–1944).

    Google Scholar 

  17. Wittgenstein’s reflections on Frazer, recently published as a slim volume (Remarks on Frazer’s Golden Bough [Atlantic Highlands, N.J.: Humanities, 1979]), are fascinating. Winch hints at all this in his elusive and allusive paper in The Philosophy of Karl Popper, ed. Schilpp. The example he gives is understanding the “force” of the reasons Sorel offered for supporting the General Strike: “the force of these ‘reasons’ could be understood only by someone who was familiar with the particular character of the movement within which it was offered” (p. 903) (the anarchosyndicalist movement). Winch’s statement (on the same page) that “to understand such situations, we have to understand the peculiar character of these institutions and people’s participation in them… a kind of understanding quite different from anything that Popper gives an account of,” is something of an understatement. For although Popper’s logic of the situation reconstructs understanding, it does so in a critical spirit, seeking typicalities as well as peculiarities in the situation, governed by the problem at hand, not treating any position as privileged, and so denying any special understanding to the participants.

    Google Scholar 

  18. Namely, Winch’s castigation of Evans-Pritchard in “Understanding a Primitive Society,” American Philosophical Quarterly 1 (1964): 307–324, and the immense literature of debate this has generated, which can be tracked through the Philosopher’s Index, and the widely scattered writings of Robin Horton, Ernest Gellner, Steven Lukes, Martin Hollis. John Skorupski, and myself.

    Google Scholar 

  19. V. Turner, The Forest of Symbols (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1967).

    Google Scholar 

  20. Mary Douglas, Purity and Danger (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1965), Natural Symbols (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1970), Implicit Meanings (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1975). More recently, see Edmund Leach, Culture and Communication (Santa Monica, Calif: Goodyear, 1979). Agassi and I have offered transcendental criticism of this position in “The Problem of the Rationality of Magic” and “Magic and Rationality Again,” both in British Journal of Sociology 18 (1967): 55–74, and 24 (1973): 236–245. Severe criticism is already to be found in Walter Kaufmann, Critique of Religion and Philosophy (New York: Harper & Row, 1958).

    Google Scholar 

  21. W. V. O. Quine, Word and Object (Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1960), p. 27. For a useful guide to Quine’s view (no straightforward matter).

    Google Scholar 

  22. see Christopher Hookway, “Indeterminacy and Translation,” in Action and Interpretation, ed. Christopher Hookway and Philip Pettit (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. 1978).

    Google Scholar 

  23. This would generate some obvious criticisms of the views of Max Weber, The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism (London: Allen and Unwin, 1930).

    Google Scholar 

  24. and R. H. Tawney, Religion and the Rise of Capitalism (New York: Harcourt Brace. 1924/1926).

    Google Scholar 

  25. Bartley, The Retreat to Commitment (New York: Knopf, 1962); “Rationality versus the Theory of Rationality,” in The Critical Approach to Science and Philosophy, ed. M. Bunge (New York: Free Press, 1964).

    Google Scholar 

  26. See the papers by Agassi and myself, “Problem of the Rationality” and “Magic and Rationality,” and the work of J. H. M. Beattie to which we refer there.

    Google Scholar 

  27. E. E. Evans-Pritchard, Witchcraft, Oracles and Magic among the Azande (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1937).

    Google Scholar 

  28. See the literature indicated in note 17.

    Google Scholar 

  29. I have had to reconstruct wholly the argument from interests, since I find much of the literature obfuscating and unquotable. Recently, P. K. Feyerabend has espoused it: see Against Method (London: New Left Books, 1975).

    Google Scholar 

  30. Francis Bacon bluntly declared the aim of science to be power over nature, in Novum Organum, and added that truth was the best means to power. He also alluded to God’s promise to Noah of domination over nature as a warrant.

    Google Scholar 

  31. On what could not possibly be otherwise, see my “The Notion of a Social Science,” in Recent Approaches to the Social Sciences, ed. H. K. Betz (Calgary: Calgary University Press, 1980), esp. sec. 3.

    Google Scholar 

  32. The private language argument is essentialist, turning on what language is and does, or must minimally be or do. If we refuse to place such stress on the words “language” and “private,” then the talk of the San Diego twins Gracie and Ginny (see Jean-Pierre Gorin’s documentary film Poto and Cabengo, 1979), speaking in tongues, and even Wittgenstein’s own coded (and now, we understand, deciphered) notebooks, can be treated as private languages.

    Google Scholar 

  33. Arthur Jensen, Bias in Mental Testing (London: Methuen, 1980).

    Google Scholar 

  34. Consider the argument in R. P. Wolff and H. Marcuse, A Critique of Pure Tolerance (Boston: Beacon, 1970), where tolerance of freedom and democracy is to be restricted because they are vulnerable to fascism.

    Google Scholar 

  35. I have discussed Mannheim in Concepts and Society, chap. 5.

    Google Scholar 

  36. The principal literature is cited at p. 495, note 29, in Philosophy of the Social Sciences 9 (1979).

    Google Scholar 

  37. An entire literature on this topic has grown out of the work of Robert K. Merton and is now being added to by the Edinburgh group and some ethnomethodologists, for example, such recent volumes as Roy Wallis, ed., On the Margins of Science (London: University of Keele, 1979).

    Google Scholar 

  38. Bruno Latour and S. W. Woolgar, Laboratory Life (Beverly Hills, Calif.: Sage, 1979).

    Google Scholar 

  39. and Barry Barnes and Steve Shapin, eds., Natural Order (Beverly Hills, Calif.: Sage, 1979).

    Google Scholar 

  40. L. Laudan offers some further criticism in “Views of Progress: Separating the Pilgrims from the Rakes,” Philosophy of the Social Sciences 10 (1980): 273–286.

    Google Scholar 

  41. This reading of Thomas Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1962).

    Google Scholar 

  42. Thomas Kuhn is developed in my “Laudan’s Problematic Progress and the Social Sciences,” Philosophy of the Social Sciences 9 (1979): 484–497.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  43. Thomas Kuhn and my review of Kuhn’s The Essential Tension, in Queen’s Quarterly 87 (1980): 65–68.

    Google Scholar 

  44. In his “Normal Science and Its Dangers,” in Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, ed. I. Lakatos and A. Musgrave (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1970), Popper writes: “Professor Kuhn’s criticism of my views about science is the most interesting one I have so far come across” (p. 51).

    Google Scholar 

  45. Recent more healthy trends in Soviet anthropology are chronicled by Ernest Gellner in the conference volume Soviet and Western Anthropology (London, 1980), and his papers, “State before Class, the Soviet Treatment of African Feudalism,” European Journal of Sociology 18 (1977): 299–322, and “Soviets against Wittfogel,” forthcoming.

    Google Scholar 

  46. See Section 1 of Bartley’s “Popperian Harvest” in the present volume.

    Google Scholar 

  47. D. F. Pears argues in his Bertrand Russell and the British Tradition in Philosophy (London: Collins, 1967) that after early Russell the torch of British empiricism passes to Wittgenstein and his followers.

    Google Scholar 

  48. Examples are: John Canfield and Keith Lehrer, “A Note on Prediction and Deduction,” Philosophy of Science 28 (1961): 204–208.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  49. R. H. Vincent, “The Paradox of Ideal Evidence,” Philosophical Review 71 (1962): 497–503.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  50. A. Grunbaum, “The Falsifiability of Scientific Theories,” Mind 73 (1964): 434–436; after 1967 further examples can be found through the Philosopher’s Index.

    Google Scholar 

  51. In this respect I fully endorse the sociological discussion in Ernest Gellner’s Words and Things (London: Gollancz, 1959; Routledge, 1979).

    Google Scholar 

  52. Carnap’s “Testability and Meaning” included Popper as one of the gang in a manner that somewhat pleased Popper at the time (see his comments in “The Demarcation between Science and Metaphysics,” in Conjectures and Refutations [London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1963], p. 255; and pp. 968ff. of “Replies”) but that obscured his very deep differences with the Vienna Circle and thwarted his subsequent efforts to dissociate himself from their concerns. (See the whole discussion of this in secs. 2 and 3 of “Replies.”)

    Google Scholar 

  53. Important exceptions are P. D. Shaw, “Popper, Historicism, and the Remaking of Society,” Philosophy of the Social Sciences 1 (1971): 299–308.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  54. John Passmore, “The Poverty of Historicism Revisited,” History and Theory, vol. 14, Essays on Historicism, pp. 30–47; Peter Urbach, “Is Any of Popper’s Arguments against Historicism Valid?” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 29 (1978): 117–130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  55. Astonishingly, there is a recent counterexample in the British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, a journai Popper helped found, and which has long been known as a forum for his ideas and those of his followers. See Mark Wilson, “Maxwell’s Condition—Goodman’s Problem,” British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 30 (1979): 107–123.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1986 D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht, Holland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Jarvie, I.C. (1986). Popper on the Difference between the Natural and the Social Sciences. In: Thinking about Society: Theory and Practice. Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol 93. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-5424-3_5

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-5424-3_5

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-94-010-8894-7

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-009-5424-3

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics